Skip to main content

Is There an Imitative Ratio Legis, and if so, How Many Are There? Psychological Perspective

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ratio Legis

Abstract

This paper seeks to demonstrate that certain ratio legis in democratic countries where the rule of law is well established is inadmissible in view of its imitative nature. Imitative ratio legis is the purpose of the legislator that aims at an ostensible solution of a social problem. Ostensibility means absence of will on the part of the legislator to have their activity produce effects. The only thing in evidence is an intention to engender a conviction among the addressees of the norms that such an effect does arise.

If we agree that ostensibility is inadmissible, then the question is in what way we can reject imitative ratio legis. We discuss three types of reasons in support of inadmissibility of imitative ratio legis. These are as follows: first, given non-compliance of legislation with the moral standards of the political community (Dworkin); second, in view of the imitative goal of the legislator or absence of a link between a prescribed/prohibited behaviour and the ostensible nature of the legislator’s goal (Fuller); third, lack of conventional-moral relationship between the substance of a prescriptive provision and the goal of the legislator (MacCormick).

All of these types of reasons rely on three assumptions: moral community of judges exist; judges possess special moral competences in assessing which ratio legis is admissible and which is not; their moral reasoning can be characterised as rational. We argue that in the light of the achievements of contemporary moral psychology, above mentioned assumptions are at least doubtful. We are of the opinion that when formulating moral judgments, judges are not equipped with any special moral competence for settling moral dilemmas. We are of the view that since people are usually unaware of the factors affecting their moral judgment, we may assume that judges are similarly unaware of what drives their moral judgments about inadmissibility of ratio legis, and thus the assumption that their decisions are rational is mistaken. If we assume that contemporary findings of moral psychology as to the role of intuitions in the moral judgments are correct, one arrives at an obvious and ‘classic’ question about which manner of argumentation should be adopted in order to convince the doubtful. Some hope can be found in reasoning based on the idea of public reason.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Journal of Laws of 2015, item 2217.

  2. 2.

    Dworkin (1986), p. 178.

  3. 3.

    Raban (2015), p. 26.

  4. 4.

    Dworkin (1986), p. 178.

  5. 5.

    Fuller (1964), pp. 46–88.

  6. 6.

    Fuller (1964), pp. 77–78.

  7. 7.

    MacCormick (2007), p. 18.

  8. 8.

    Gizbert-Studnicki et al. (2016), pp. 343–344.

  9. 9.

    See e.g. Mancini and Rosenfeld (2010).

  10. 10.

    Waldron (2009), pp. 2–4.

  11. 11.

    Sadurski (2009), pp. 26–45.

  12. 12.

    Kohlberg (1968), pp. 25–30.

  13. 13.

    LoBue et al. (2011), pp. 154–170.

  14. 14.

    Kahneman (2011), p. 11.

  15. 15.

    Tyszka (2010), p. 17.

  16. 16.

    Redelmeier and Kahneman (1996), pp. 3–8.

  17. 17.

    Kahneman (2000), pp. 673–674.

  18. 18.

    Kahneman and Tversky (1972), pp. 430–454.

  19. 19.

    Tyszka (2010), p. 238.

  20. 20.

    Tyszka (1999), p. 145.

  21. 21.

    Haidt (2014), p. 69.

  22. 22.

    Margolis (1990), pp. 13 et seq.

  23. 23.

    Mercier and Sperber (2011), pp. 57–111.

  24. 24.

    Greene et al. (2004), pp. 389–400.

  25. 25.

    Greene et al. (2004), pp. 395–400.

  26. 26.

    Baron and Ritov (1994), pp. 133–167.

  27. 27.

    Sunstein (2005), pp. 531–573.

  28. 28.

    Mikhail (2007), pp. 143–152. Also: Greene et al. (2008), pp. 1144–1154; Cummins and Cummins (2012), pp. 1–16.

  29. 29.

    Bartels (2008), pp. 381–417. See also: Koenigs et al. (2007), pp. 908–911.

  30. 30.

    Bartels and Pizarro (2011), pp. 154–161.

  31. 31.

    Moore et al. (2008), pp. 549–557.

  32. 32.

    Greene et al. (2008), pp. 1144–1154.

  33. 33.

    Greene et al. (2001), pp. 2105–2108.

  34. 34.

    Rawls (2001) pp. 1–19.

  35. 35.

    Smolak (2015), pp. 89–96.

  36. 36.

    Rawls (1999), pp. 133–134.

  37. 37.

    den Otter (2005), p. 336.

  38. 38.

    See above, p. 356.

  39. 39.

    den Otter (2009), pp. 18–22.

References

  • Baron J, Ritov I (1994) Protected values and omission bias as deontological judgments. Psychol Learn Motiv 50:133–167

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartels D (2008) Principled moral sentiment and the flexibility of moral judgment in decision making. Cognition 108:381–417

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartels D, Pizarro D (2011) The mismeasure of morals: antisocial personality traits predict utilitarian responses to moral dilemmas. Cognition 121:154–161

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins D, Cummins R (2012) Emotion and deliberative reasoning in moral judgment. Front Psychol 3:1–16

    Google Scholar 

  • den Otter R (2005) Can a liberal take his own side in an argument? The case for John Rawls’s idea of political liberalism. Saint Louis Law J 49:336

    Google Scholar 

  • den Otter R (2009) Judicial review in the age of moral pluralism. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 15–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller L (1964) The morality of law. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Gizbert-Studnicki T, Dyrda A, Grabowski A (2016) Metodologiczne dychotomie. Krytyka pozytywistycznych teorii prawa (Methodological dychotomies. Critics of positivistic legal theories). Wolters Kluwer, Warsaw

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene J, Sommerville R, Nystrom L, Darley J, Cohen J (2001) An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293:2105–2108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene J, Nystrom L, Engell A, Darley A, Cohen L (2004) The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron 44(2):389–400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene J, Morelli S, Lowenberg K, Nystrom L, Cohen J (2008) Cognitive load selectivity interferes with utilitarian moral judgment. Cognition 107:144–1154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2014) Prawy umysł. Dlaczego dobrych ludzi dzieli religia i polityka? (The righteous mind: why good people divided by politics and religion?). Smak Slowa, Sopot

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2000) Experienced utility and objective happiness: a moment-based approach. In: Kahneman D, Tversky A (eds) Choices, values and frames. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2011) Thinking, fast and slow. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Tversky A (1972) A subjective probability: a judgment of representativeness. Cogn Psychol 3:430–454

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenigs M, Young L, Adolphs R, Tranel D, Cushman F, Hauser M, Damasio A (2007) A damage to prefrontal cortex increases utilitarian moral judgments. Nature 446:908–911

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg L (1968) The child as a moral philosopher. Psychol Today 2(4):25–30

    Google Scholar 

  • LoBue V, Nishida T, Chiong C, DeLoache JS, Haidt J (2011) When getting something good is bad: even three-year-olds react to inequality. Soc Dev 20:154–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick N (2007) Institutions of law. An essay in legal theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mancini S, Rosenfeld M (2010) The judge as moral arbiter? The case of abortion. In: Sajó A, Uitz R (eds) Constitutional topography: values and constitutions. https://ssrn.com/abstract=1721644

  • Margolis H (1990) Patterns, thinking and cognition. A theory of judgment. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier H, Sperber D (2011) Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behav Brain Sci 34:57–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail J (2007) Universal moral grammar: theory, evidence and the future. Trends Cogn Sci 11:143–152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore A, Clark B, Kane M (2008) Who shalt not kill? Individual difference in working memory capacity, executive control, and moral judgment. Psychol Sci 8:549–557

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raban O (2015) The rationalization of policy: on the relation between democracy and the rule of law. N Y Univ J Legislation Public Policy. https://ssrn.com/abstract=2564548 or https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2564548, p 52

  • Rawls J (1999) The idea of public reason revisited in: the law of peoples. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (2001) Collected papers. In: Freeman S (ed) Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Redelmeier DA, Kahneman D (1996) Patient’s memories of painful medical treatments: real-time and retrospective evaluations of two minimally invasive procedures. Pain 66(1):3–8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadurski W (2009) Rights and moral reasoning: an unstated assumption – a comment on Jeremy Waldron’s “Judges as moral reasoners”. Int J Const L 1(7):26–45

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolak M (2015) The method of reflective equilibrium in moral reasoning. Arch Philos Law Soc Philos 1:89–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein C (2005) Moral heuristics. Behav Brain Sci 28:531–573

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyszka T (1999) Psychologiczne pułapki oceniania i podejmowania decyzji (Psychological traps of judgement and decision). GWP, Gdańsk

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyszka T (2010) Decyzje. Perspektywa psychologiczna i ekonomiczna (Decisions-psychological and economic perspective). Scholar, Warsaw

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2009) Judges as moral reasoners. Int J Const L 1(7):2–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Teresa Chirkowska-Smolak .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Chirkowska-Smolak, T., Smolak, M. (2018). Is There an Imitative Ratio Legis, and if so, How Many Are There? Psychological Perspective. In: Klappstein, V., Dybowski, M. (eds) Ratio Legis. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-74271-7_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-74271-7_7

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-74270-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-74271-7

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics