Skip to main content

Mathematical Truth Regained

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Phenomenology and Mathematics

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 195))

Abstract

Benacerraf’s Dilemma (BD), as formulated by Paul Benacerraf in “Mathematical Truth,” is about the apparent impossibility of reconciling a “standard” (i.e., classical Platonic) semantics of mathematics with a “reasonable” (i.e., causal, spatiotemporal) epistemology of cognizing true statements. In this paper I spell out a new solution to BD. I call this new solution a positive Kantian phenomenological solution for three reasons: (1) It accepts Benacerraf’s preliminary philosophical assumptions about the nature of semantics and knowledge, as well as all the basic steps of BD, and then shows how we can, consistently with those very assumptions and premises, still reject the skeptical conclusion of BD and also adequately explain mathematical knowledge. (2) The standard semantics of mathematically necessary truth that I offer is based on Kant’s philosophy of arithmetic, as interpreted by Charles Parsons and by me. (3) The reasonable epistemology of mathematical knowledge that I offer is based on the phenomenology of logical and mathematical self-evidence developed by early Husserl in Logical Investigations and by early Wittgenstein in Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    (Milton, 1953b, 495, book I, lines 1–7)

  2. 2.

    (Parsons 2008, 166)

  3. 3.

    (LI, pp. 765 and 787, texts combined)

  4. 4.

    (Wittgenstein, 1981, prop. 5.4731, p. 129)

  5. 5.

    In (Hanna, 2006a Chapters 6 and 7), I work out Kant’s idea that mathematical knowledge is grounded on reflective self-consciousness together with the imagination.

  6. 6.

    One way of doing this would be via “plenitudinous platonism”: For every consistently imaginable mathematical statement, there is a corresponding mathematical object. (See, e.g., Balaguer, 1998.) This construes imaginability as conceivability. But there are other ways of thinking about the imagination, e.g., Kant’s conception of the productive imagination as a “schematizing” (i.e., mental modeling) capacity (Kant 1997, A84–147/B116–187, and esp. A120 n.). In (Hanna, 2006b, Chapter 6), I extend BD to logical knowledge, and then develop a strategy for solving the extended BD that starts with the thesis that a reasonable epistemology should be modeled on the imagination, not on perception. So by the classification scheme described here, strictly speaking, that earlier solution counts as a pre-emptive negative or skeptical solution. But to the extent that the present solution postulates the innate presence of mental modeling abilities in sense perception, it also postulates the innate presence of the capacity for imagination within the capacity for sense perception. So in that sense, the present positive or anti-skeptical solution is really only an extension and refinement of the earlier solution.

  7. 7.

    (See Benacerraf, 1965). This problem, in turn, is closely connected to Frege’s “Caesar” problem. (See Frege, 1953, p. 68.)

  8. 8.

    See (and hear) (Numminen, 2009).

  9. 9.

    (Milton, 1953a, p. 487, book XII, lines 641–649).

  10. 10.

    I am very grateful to the organizers (especially Mirja Hartimo, Leila Haaparanta, Juliette Kennedy, and Sara Heinämaa) of and also the participants in (especially William Tait), the Phenomenology and Mathematics conference at the University of Tampere, Finland in May 07, where I presented an earlier version of this paper, for all their help—critical, editorial, philosophical, and otherwise.

References

  • Balaguer, M. 1998. Platonism and Anti-Platonism in Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. 1965. What Numbers Could Not Be. Philosophical Review 74: 47–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. 1973. Mathematical Truth. Journal of Philosophy 70: 661–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. 1996. What Mathematical Truth Could Not Be – I. In Benacerraf and his Critics, eds. A. Morton and S. P. Stich, 9–59. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 1980a. Troubles with Functionalism. In Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, ed. N. Block, Vol 1, 268–305. Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 1980b. What is Functionalism? In Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, ed. N. Block, Vol. 1, 171–184. Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. and Logue, H. (eds.) 2009. Disjunctivism: Contemporary Readings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 1986. Knowledge of Language. Westport, CN: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. 1980. Science without Numbers: A Defense of Nominalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. 1989. Realism, Mathematics, and Modality. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1953. Foundations of Arithmetic. 2nd edition, Trans. J.L. Austin. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giaquinto, M. 2007. Visual Thinking in Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haddock, A. and McPherson, F. (eds.) 2008. Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. 1987. Abstract Objects. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. and Wright, C. 2001. The Reason’s Proper Study. Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. and Wright, C. 2002. Benacerraf’s Dilemma Revisited. European Journal of Philosophy 10: 101–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R. 2001. Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R. 2002. Mathematics for Humans: Kant’s Philosophy of Arithmetic Revisited. European Journal of Philosophy 10: 328–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R. 2006a. Kant, Science, and Human Nature. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R. 2006b. Rationality and the Ethics of Logic. Journal of Philosophy 103: 67–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R. 2006c. Rationality and Logic. MA: MIT Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R. and Maiese, M. 2009. Embodied Minds in Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1996. Mental Causation. Mind 105: 377–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1997. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. P. Guyer and A. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press. When citing the first Critique, I follow the common practice of giving page numbers from the A (1781) and B (1787) German editions only.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, J. 1995. What Mathematical Knowledge Could Be. Mind 104: 491–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 2006. Philosophy of Mind. 2nd edition. Boulder: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. 1982. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. 2006. On Being Alienated. In Perceptual Experience, eds. T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne, 354–410. Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Milton, J. 1953a. Paradise Lost. In The Poems of John Milton. 2nd edition, ed. J. Milton, 204–487. New York: Ronald Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milton, J. 1953b. Paradise Regained. In The Poems of John Milton. 2nd edition, ed. J. Milton, 495–544. New York: Ronald Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Numminen, M. A. 2009. Wovon Man Nicht Sprechen Kann, Darüber Muss Man Schweigen. At ULR = http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=57PWqFowq-4.

  • Parsons, C. 1983. Kant’s Philosophy of Arithmetic. In Mathematics in Philosophy, C. Parsons, 119–149. New York: Cornell Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, C. 2008. Mathematical Thought and its Objects. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potter, M. 1990. Sets: An Introduction. Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford Univ Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potter, M.. 2000. Reason’s Nearest Kin. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D. L. 1990. Perceptual Representation Systems and Implicit Memory: Towards a Resolution of the Multiple Memory Systems Debate. Annals of the New York Academy of Science 608: 543–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. 1984. Minds, Brains, and Science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. 1997. Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology. New York: Oxford Univ Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. 1998. Induction and Indefinite Extensibility: The Gödel Sentence is True, But Did Someone Change the Subject? Mind 107: 597–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. 2000. Thinking about Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skolem, T. 1967. The foundations of elementary arithmetic established by means of the recursive mode of thought, without the use of apparent variables ranging over infinite domains. In From Frege to Gödel, ed. J. van Heijenoort. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Struik, D. J. 1967. A Concise History of Mathematics. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Troelstra, A. S. and Dalen, D. V. 1998. Constructivism in Mathematics: An Introduction, vol. 1. Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1981. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, Trans. C.K. Ogden. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1983. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. 2nd edition, Trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. 1983. Frege’s Conception of Numbers as Objects. Aberdeen: Aberdeen Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hanna, R. (2010). Mathematical Truth Regained. In: Hartimo, M. (eds) Phenomenology and Mathematics. Phaenomenologica, vol 195. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3729-9_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics