Skip to main content

Type Theory and Lexical Decomposition

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Advances in Generative Lexicon Theory

Part of the book series: Text, Speech and Language Technology ((TLTB,volume 46))

Abstract

In this chapter, I explore the relation between methods of lexical representation involving decomposition and the theory of types as used in linguistics and programming semantics. I identify two major approaches to lexical decomposition in grammar, what I call parametric and predicative strategies. I demonstrate how expressions formed with one technique can be translated into expressions of the other. I then discuss argument selection within a type theoretic approach to semantics, and show how the predicative approach to decomposition can be modeled within a type theory with richer selectional mechanisms. In particular, I show how classic Generative Lexicon representations and operations can be viewed in terms of types and selection.

The framework developed here is extended to a broader classes of coercion types in the context of argument selection in Pustejovsky (2011).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The admission that mentalese appears to be a first order language is already an acceptance that some sort of decomposition is desirable or necessary for describing language. But beyond this, we will see that the vocabulary accepted as standard to discuss verb behavior is a further commitment to types or categories as part of lexical descriptions.

  2. 2.

    Each of these strategies has been thoroughly explored in the literature. What I hope to illustrate here is the organization of these approaches according to the above classification. The focus in the discussion below will be on verbs and their projection to syntactic form.

  3. 3.

    This is the \( \theta \)-theory in varieties of Chomsky’s framework from the 1980s, and the Functional Uniqueness Principle from LFG.

  4. 4.

    For the present discussion, I assume that the subpredicates in the expressions below are related by means of standard first order logical connectives.

  5. 5.

    The neo-Davidsonian position adopted by Kratzer (1994) does not fall into this category, but rather in the supralexical decomposition category below. Reasons for this will become clear in the discussion that follows.

  6. 6.

    Whether the concept of married is any less complex than that of the definiendum bachelor has, of course, been a matter of some dispute. Cf. Weinreich (1972).

  7. 7.

    Recall that such collapsing operations were an important process prior to lexical insertion in Generative Semantics, cf. McCawley 1972; Dowty 1979.

  8. 8.

    In programming languages, the operation of semantic analysis verifies that the typing assignments associated with expressions are valid. This is essentially done in compilation time, as a pre-test, filtering out arguments that would otherwise have the wrong type. In a model that does not perform predicate decomposition to incorporate typing constraints, sentences like (19b) are just false.

  9. 9.

    Regarding argument selection, there are two possible strategies for how the argument accommodates to the typing requirement. Given that the type requirement is a pretest, the argument expression can fail (strict monomorphic typing), or coerce to the appropriate type (polymorphic typing). We will not discuss coercion in the context of the fail early strategy in this paper.

  10. 10.

    This brings up the issue of how a pre-test is related to the presuppositional interpretation of argument selection. Although an important question, I will defer discussion to a forthcoming treatment of selection mechanisms, Pustejovsky (forthcoming).

  11. 11.

    This class of adjectives has been studied extensively. Bouillon (1997) analyzes such constructions as subselective predication of a qualia role in the head. Larson and Cho (2003) provide a more conventional interpretation without the need for decompositional representations.

  12. 12.

    In both (40b) and (40c), interpretations are possible with modification over the object, but they are semantically marked with bright and contradictory with long.

  13. 13.

    It is worth noting that the propositions formed by the composition of a natural predicate with natural type entities have a special status, since they form the basis of what we will call natural propositions. Examples of such propositions are given below:

    • The rabbit died.

    • The rock touches the water.

    • The ants are under the tree.

    It is interesting to compare this to Anscombe’s (1958) discussion and Searle’s (1995) extension regarding “brute facts” as opposed to “institutional facts.”. The natural predication of a property over a natural entity is a judgment requiring no institutional context or background. Facts (or at least judgments) can be classified according to the kinds of participant they contain; in fact, as we shall see, the qualia and the principle of type ordering will allow us to enrich this “fact classification” even further.

  14. 14.

    Dipert makes a similar move in his 1993 book Artifacts, Art Works, and Agency.

  15. 15.

    The judgments expressed by the predication of an artifactual predicate of an artifactual subject results in an artifactual proposition. This is formally similar to Searle’s notion of institutional fact.

  16. 16.

    It might be possible to view pure selection as incorporating the accommodation rule as well, which would result in a more symmetric distribution of behavior in the table. Whether this is computationally desirable, however, is still unclear.

  17. 17.

    Exploitation on the info element of the dot object for book occurs in examples such as

    (i)

    below:

    (i)

    I don’t believe this book at all.

    Here the verb is selecting for propositional content, which is present by exploitation in the dot object of the direct object.

  18. 18.

    For the present discussion, we ignore selection of a dot object in an artifactual type context. In general, the analysis will follow the introduction rule seen in (71a) below, but there are complications in some cases. These are discussed in Pustejovsky (2011).

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). On Brute facts. Analysis, 18, 69–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Pustejovsky, J. (2005). Word meaning and commonsense metaphysics. ms. Brandeis University and University of Texas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Pustejovsky, J. (2006). A type composition logic for generative lexicon. Journal of Cognitive Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borschev, V., & Partee, B. (2001). Genitive modifiers, sorts, and metonymy. Nordic Journal of Linguistics, 24(2), 140–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouillon, P. (1997). Polymorphie et sémantique lexicale: le cas des adjectifs. Lille: Presses Universitaires du Spetentrion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Busa, F. (1996). Compositionality and the semantics of nominals. Ph.D. dissertation, Brandeis University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Busa, F., Calzolari, N., Lenci, A., & Pustejovsky, J. (1999). Building a semantic lexicon: Structuring and generating concepts. In Proceedings of IWCS-III, Tilberg, The Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, G. (1977). Reference to Kinds in English, Ph.D. dissertation. Amherst: University of Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G. (1989). Structured meanings, thematic roles, and control. In G. Chierchia, B. Partee, & R. Turner (Eds.), Properties, types, and meaning (Vol. 2, pp. 131–166). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Copestake, A., & Briscoe, T. (1992). Lexical operations. In a unification-based framework. In J. Pustejovsky & S. Bergler (Eds.), Lexical semantics and knowledge representation. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1986). Knowledge of language, its nature, origin, and use. New York: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corblin, F. (2003). Presuppositions and commitment stores in Diabruck. 7th Workshop on the semantics and the pragmatics of dialogue, 2003. Saarbruecken, Germany.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cruse, D. A. (1986). Lexical semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, A., & Koenig, J.-P. (2000). Linking as constraints on word classes in a hierarchical lexicon. Language, 76, 56–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967). The logical form of action sentences. In N. Rescher (Ed.), The logic of decision and action. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dipert, R. R. (1993). Artifacts, art works, and agency. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D. R. (1979). Word meaning and Montague grammar. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D., Wall, R., & Peters, S. (1980). Introduction to montague semantics, Synthese Language Library. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D. R. (1989). On the semantic content of the notion ‘thematic role’. In G. Chierchia, B. Partee, & R. Turner (Eds.), Properties, types, and meaning (Semantic issues, Vol. 2). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Lepore, E. (1998). The emptiness of the lexicon. Critical reflections on J. Pustejovsky’s ‘The generative lexicon’. Linguistic Inquiry, 29, 269–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fellbaum, C. (Ed.). (1998). WordNet: An electronic lexical database. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazdar, G., Klein, E., Pullum, G., & Sag, I. (1985). Generalized phrase structure grammar. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginzburg, J., & Sag, I. (2000). Interrogative investigations: the form, meaning, and use of English interrogatives. Stanford: CSLI Publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, A. (1995). Constructions: A construction grammar approach to argument structure. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gupta, A. (1980). The logic of common nouns. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I., & Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs, J., Stickel, M., Martin, P., & Edwards, D. (1993). Interpretation as abduction. Artificial Intelligence, 63, 69–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (2002). Foundations of language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H., & Partee, B. (1995). Prototype theory and compositionality. Cognition, 57(2), 129–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katz, J., & Fodor, J. (1963). The structure of a semantic theory. Language, 39, 170–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. (1989). Concepts, kinds, and cognitive development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (1994). On external arguments. In J. Runner & E. Benedicto (Eds.), Functional projections (pp. 103–129). Amherst: GLSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (1996). In J. Rooryck & L. Zaring (Eds.), Severing the external argument from its verb. Phrase structure and the lexicon (pp. 109–137). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (1965/1970). Irregularity in syntax. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson, R., & Cho, S. (2003). Temporal adjectives and the structure of possessive DPs. Natural Language Semantics, 11, 3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, B., & Rappaport Hovav, M. (2005). Argument realization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, B., & Rappaport Hovav, M. (1995). Unaccusatives: At the syntax-lexical semantics interface. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (1968). Introduction to theoretical linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marantz, A. P. (1984). On the nature of grammatical relations. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCawley, J. D. (1968). The role of semantics in a grammar. In E. Bach & R. T. Harms (Eds.), Universals in linguistic theory. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moens, M., & Steedman, M. (1988). Temporal Ontology and Temporal Reference. Computational Linguistics, 14, 15–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moravcsik, J. M. (1975). Aitia as generative factor in Aristotle’s philosophy. Dialogue, 14, 622–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1990). Events in the semantics of English. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. (1992). Syntactic categories and semantic type. In M. Rosner & R. Johnson (Eds.), Computational linguistics and formal semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B., & Borshev, V. (2001). Genitives, relational nouns, and argument-modifier ambiguity. In C. Fabricius-Hansen, E. Lang, & C. Maienborn (Eds.), Modifying adjuncts (Interface explorations). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (1989). Learnability and cognition: The acquisition of argument structure. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1991). The generative lexicon. Computational Linguistics, 17, 409–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1993). Type coercion and lexical selection. In J. Pustejovsky (Ed.), Semantics and the lexicon. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1995). The generative lexicon. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1998). The semantics of lexical underspecification. Folia Linguistica, 32, 323–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (2001). Type construction and the logic of concepts. In P. Bouillon & F. Busa (Eds.), The syntax of word meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (2005). Natural kinds in linguistics. In Festschrift for Chungmin Lee. Hankook Munhwasa Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (forthcoming). Language meaning and the logic of concepts. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (2011). Coercion in a general theory of argument selection. Journal of Linguistics, 49(6).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J., & Boguraev, B. (1993). Lexical knowledge representation and natural language processing. Artificial Intelligence, 63, 193–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Mind, language and reality (Philosophical papers, Vol. 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E. (1975). Cognitive representations of semantic categories. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 104(3), 192–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Valin, R. (2005). Exploring the syntax-semantics interface. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Weinreich, U. (1972). Explorations in semantic theory. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James Pustejovsky .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Pustejovsky, J. (2013). Type Theory and Lexical Decomposition. In: Pustejovsky, J., Bouillon, P., Isahara, H., Kanzaki, K., Lee, C. (eds) Advances in Generative Lexicon Theory. Text, Speech and Language Technology, vol 46. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5189-7_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5189-7_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-5188-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-5189-7

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics