Skip to main content

Society and the Origin of Moral Law: Giambattista Vico and Non-reductive Naturalism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
What Makes Us Moral? On the capacities and conditions for being moral

Part of the book series: Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy ((LOET,volume 31))

  • 3002 Accesses

Abstract

The dominant naturalistic tradition in moral philosophy assumes that the basic capacities and characteristics of the individual exist prior to his or her socialisation and that morality arises out of the necessity for cooperation. In order to exist peacefully in society, aggressive instincts are either redirected from external objects to the individual him or herself or the human being has a natural tendency to cooperation. There is a third alternative which avoids the problems with these accounts and also offers a way to comprehend the relationships between morality, social conventions and moral law. Giambattista Vico grounds his historical science in the faculty of imagination regulated by basic universal facts about human beings. The argument of the present paper will present the problems with reductive naturalism and outline the alternative Vichian moral sociology, projecting what the empirical consequences of this new methodology may be.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I here use ‘Hobbes’, ‘Freud’ and ‘Locke’ to stand in for standard positions, but pay little attention to the subtlety and nuances of their particular approaches. For this I apologize, but do so for reasons of expediency. For example, I believe that the indifference to at least thinking through the theological aspects of Locke’s theory does serious damage to his theory as a whole.

  2. 2.

    It should be noted that, for Locke, practical reason is ad hoc and not scientific: the justification of the moral conscience is theological in nature and hence not consistent with modern science. However, there exists a secondary justification in self-ownership in which the human being is aware of his body as his own and reciprocally realizes that others, too, own their bodies (Locke 1988, § 27). Such philosophical explanation has its counterparts in evolutionary discourse: a debate has opened up between those who believe that human cooperation and group regulations can be traced to, on the one hand, the aggressive instincts of the chimpanzee and those, on the other hand, who trace them to the social instincts of the bonobo (Peterson and Wrangham 1997; Kano and Vineberg 1992). So, it is possible to use Locke’s general description in a way consistent with natural science and independent of theological assertions.

  3. 3.

    By mentioning only Hobbes and Locke, there is a felt lack of the third principal character of modern, social contract theory, viz. Rousseau. Rousseau is more complex and like Vico he sees society as an effect of language, which Locke and Hobbes both think predates society. Unlike Vico, though, Rousseau holds that the rule of nature is innate and guarantees liberty and equality beyond social convention, rather than an imagined effect of society. There is a further ‘radical’ alternative symptomatic of Aristotelians and Hegelians in that a moral conscience is derived from social existence (like the core explanation above) but that (unlike the core explanation) social existence is natural, an organic development of our existence. Human beings naturally and necessarily exist in societies. Such an alternative cannot be considered here and can be dismissed by the terms of the present debate. Neither Hegelians nor Aristotelians are coherent with modern science. For the former, ethics and politics are part of a discourse that is inflated from poorer and simpler scientific ones (rather than reduced to it); and for the latter, explanation is based in a metaphysics wholly contradictory to modern science. Vico, as we shall hopefully see, is different because perhaps he gives us a way to link the science and morality in a different way.

  4. 4.

    Such a descriptive problem is equally true of Freud’s purely psychological description of the formation of the super-ego through the oedipal development phase. If internalization occurs through turning aggressive instincts on oneself, it can only be dependent on the equally important love of the father and not just aggression towards him. In fact, love seems stronger than aggression.

  5. 5.

    As formerly, with Hobbes and Locke, the reading of Vico offered here is pragmatic and expedient, rather than nuanced and attentive, although I do feel it is consistent and ultimately right. Closer interpretation would be required to prove this conviction of course.

  6. 6.

    All references to Vico’s writings are cited by paragraph number (§).

  7. 7.

    Vico uses the genetic-etymological method to show that the myths of Jove are then reified into ‘ius’ or Justice. So, the primal motivation to be good even if it conflicts with other interests is fear of punishment. From such sensuous beginnings, abstract notions of right and wrong are developed through historical embellishments to the irreal system of ‘moral’ nature. I cannot comment on the status of the etymological proof, though I would take it with a huge pinch of salt. See § 398.

  8. 8.

    One problem here is that my child is already socialized. He has completed 1 year of school and possesses a language. He has been taught about ‘sharing’ and ‘fairness’ since his birth.

  9. 9.

    It is very similar to Sartre’s (2003) discussions of self-consciousness as well.

References

  • Deligiorgi, K. 2010. Doing without agency: Hegel’s social theory of action. In Hegel on action, ed. A. Laitinen and C. Sandis, 97–118. London: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. 2002. Madness and its discontents. Trans. D. McLintock. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grassi, E. 1976. Marxism, humanism, and the problem of imagination in Vico’s work. In Giambattista Vico’s science of humanity, ed. G. Tagliacozzo and D. Verene, 275–294. Baltimore: John Hopkins Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. 1996. Leviathan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1997. From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kano, T., and E. Vineberg. 1992. The last ape: Pygmy chimpanzee behavior and ecology. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. 1988. Two treatises of government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, D., and R. Wrangham. 1997. Demonic males: Apes and the origins of human violence. New York: Mariner Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. 2003. Facts, values, and norms: Essays toward a morality of consequence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.-J. 1984. A discourse on inequality. Trans. M. Cranston. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. 2003. Being and nothingness. Trans. H. Barnes. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verene, D. 2008. Vichian moral philosophy: Prudence as jurisprudence. The Chicago-Kent Law Review 83(3): 1107–1130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vico, G. 1982. The first new science: The principles of a new science of the nature of nations leading to the discovery of the principles of a new system of the natural law of the gentes [1725]. In Vico’s selected writings (trans and ed.: Pompa, L), 81–156. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vico, G. 1984. The new science of Giambattista Vico, 3rd ed, ed. T. Bergin and M. Fisch. New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Edward Rose .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rose, D.E. (2013). Society and the Origin of Moral Law: Giambattista Vico and Non-reductive Naturalism. In: Musschenga, B., van Harskamp, A. (eds) What Makes Us Moral? On the capacities and conditions for being moral. Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy, vol 31. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6343-2_18

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics