Skip to main content

Non-genetic Inheritance and Evolution

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Philosophy of Biology

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 1))

Abstract

Teaching evolution usually means an exclusive focus on transmission genetics as the basis for heredity. The stability of DNA sequences gives the impression that the developmental history of individuals can be set aside and evolutionary change in phenotypes can be described as change in gene frequencies. This is the textbook version of evolution and the view that the majority of evolutionary biologists subscribe to. The unique position of DNA in heredity is now being challenged, however. Mounting empirical evidence suggests that phenotypic stability within lineages and differences between lineages can originate and be maintained via epigenetic and behavioural mechanisms, even in the absence of genetic variation. This raises questions regarding the evolutionary implications of such non-genetic mechanisms of inheritance, including whether they can bias the rate and direction of evolution or allow inheritance of acquired characters. In this chapter, I outline the historical background to the development of the transmission genetics view of heredity and how recent findings in molecular, developmental, and behavioural biology challenge the textbooks. I continue by showing how the heterogeneous cluster of non-genetic mechanisms of inheritance can contribute to an expanded version of evolutionary theory. Although it turns out that the special role played by genes in evolution can also be played by other inheritance systems, the main conceptual advantage of recognizing non-genetic mechanisms of inheritance is that it stimulates an explicit consideration of developmental processes in evolutionary explanations. This helps us to connect the processes responsible for within-generation change (‘proximate questions’ or the domain of developmental biology) with among-generation change (‘ultimate question’ or the domain of evolutionary biology). Furthermore, it shows how the teaching of fundamental concepts in evolutionary biology can benefit from philosophical analysis informed by contemporary biological research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    These examples share the common feature that, when parents transmit more than genes to their offspring, what is selected and what is transmitted to future generations can be decoupled, and phenotypes in one generation may change the developmental context (and hence the selective regime) of future generations. When only genes are transmitted, selection directly controls all forms of heritable variation, which precludes investigation of many interesting forms of feedback between organism and environment.

  2. 2.

    The Price Equation is a mathematical formulation about change in a population from one generation to the next (Price 1970; see Gardner 2008 for a non-technical introduction). It is usually written in a form that separates the change in a particular trait value into two terms. The first describes the change due to selection, whereas the second describes the expected difference in trait value between parents and offspring (e.g., based on the mechanism of inheritance; Helanterä and Uller 2010; Day and Bonduriansky 2011).

References

  • Allen, G.E. 1978. Thomas Hunt Morgan: The man and his science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G.E. 1983. T.H. Morgan and the influence of mechanistic materialism on the development of the gene concept 1910–1940. American Zoologist 23: 829–843.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alters, B.J., and C.E. Nelson. 2002. Perspective: Teaching evolution in higher education. Evolution 56: 1891–1901.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. 2005. The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought. Structure and synthesis. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, W. 2010. Evolution: A developmental approach. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avital, E., and E. Jablonka. 2000. Animal traditions. Behavioural inheritance in evolution. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Badyaev, A.V. 2009. Evolutionary significance of phenotypic accommodation in novel environments: An empirical test of the Baldwin effect. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 364: 1125–1141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Badyaev, A.V. 2011. Origin of the fittest: Link between emergent variation and evolutionary change as a critical question in evolutionary biology. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 278: 1921–1929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Badyaev, A.V., and T. Uller. 2009. Parental effects in ecology and evolution: Mechanisms, processes and implications. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 364: 1169–1177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, J.M. 1902. Development and evolution. New York: Macmillan & Co. Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergstrom, C.T., and M. Rosvall. 2011. The transmission sense of information. Biology and Philosophy 26: 159–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonduriansky, R. 2012. Rethinking heredity, again. Trends in Ecology & Evolution 27: 330–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourke, A.F.G. 2011. Principles of social evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., and P.J. Richerson. 2005. The origins and evolution of cultures. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, E.O. 2011. Mutation. The history of an idea from Darwin to genomics. Cold Spring Harbor: CSH Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavalli-Sforza, L.L., and M.W. Feldman. 1981. Cultural transmission and evolution: A quantitative approach. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Champagne, F.A., and J.P. Curley. 2012. Genetic and epigenetics of parental care. In Evolution of parental care, ed. N. Royle, P.T. Smiseth, and M. Kölliker, 304–324. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheverud, J.M., and J.B. Wolf. 2009. The genetics and evolutionary consequences of maternal effects. In Maternal effects in mammals, ed. D. Maestripieri and J.M. Mateo, 11–37. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. 1979. Maternal constraints in development. In Maternal effects in development, ed. D.R. Newth and M. Balls, 1–28. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danchin, É., A. Charmantier, F.A. Champagne, A. Mesoudi, B. Pujol, and S. Blanchet. 2011. Beyond DNA: Integrating inclusive inheritance into an extended theory of evolution. Nature Reviews Genetics 12: 475–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. 1868. The variation of animals and plants under domestication. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. 1976. The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Day, T., and R. Bonduriansky. 2011. A unified approach to the evolutionary consequences of genetic and nongenetic inheritance. The American Naturalist 178: E18–E36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, T. 1937. Genetics and the origin of species. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, M.J. 2009. Closing the gap: Inverting the genetics curriculum to ensure an informed public. American Journal of Human Genetics 85: 6–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. 2009. Genetic analysis. A history of genetic thinking. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R.A. 1930. The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton, F. 1876. A theory of heredity. Journal of the Anthropological Institute 5: 329–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, A. 2008. The Price equation. Current Biology 18: R198–R202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, A. 2011. Kin selection under blending inheritance. Journal of Theoretical Biology 284: 125–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S.F., and D. Epel. 2009. Ecological developmental biology. Integrating epigenetics, medicine and evolution. Sunderland: Sinauer Associates Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gissis, S.B., and E. Jablonka. 2011. Transformations of Lamarckism: From subtle fluids to molecular biology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2009. Darwinian populations and natural selection. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2011. Senders, receivers, and genetic information: Comments on Bergstrom and Rosvall. Biology and Philosophy 26: 171–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, G. 1992. Individual development and evolution. The genesis of novel behavior. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E., and R.D. Gray. 1994. Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. Journal of Philosophy 91: 277–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, Paul E., and Karola Stotz. 2007. Gene. In Cambridge companion to philosophy of biology, ed. Michael Ruse and David Hull, 85–102. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, W.D. 1964. The genetical evolution of social behavior. Journal of Theoretical Biology 7(1): 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helanterä, H., and T. Uller. 2010. The Price equation and extended inheritance. Philosophy and Theory in Biology 2: 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M.J.S. 1985. Darwin as a lifelong generation theorist. In The Darwinian heritage, ed. D. Kohn, 207–243. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, J. 1942. Evolution. The modern synthesis. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E. 2002. Information: Its interpretation, its inheritance, and its sharing. Philosophy of Science 69: 578–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., and M. Lamb. 1995. Epigenetic inheritance and evolution. The Lamarckian dimension. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., and M. Lamb. 2005. Evolution in four dimensions. Genetic, epigenetic, behavioral and symbolic variation in the history of life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., and M.J. Lamb. 2006. The evolution of information in the major transitions. Journal of Theoretical Biology 239: 236–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., and G. Raz. 2009. Transgenerational epigenetic inheritance: Prevalence, mechanisms, and implications for the study of heredity and evolution. The Quarterly Review of Biology 84: 131–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen, W. 1909. Elemente der exacten Erblichkeitslehre. Jena: Gustav Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K. 2013a. Mendel and the path to genetics: Portraying science as a social process. Science & Education 22(2–3): 293–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K. 2013b. Teaching about adaptation: Why evolutionary history matters. Science & Education 22(2–3): 173–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K., and V. Zogza. 2009. Preliminary evolutionary explanations: A basic framework for conceptual change and explanatory coherence in evolution. Science & Education 18: 1313–1340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K.N., K. Sterelny, J. Odling-Smee, W. Hoppitt, and T. Uller. 2011. Cause and effect in biology revisited: Is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science 334: 1512–1516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K.N., J. Odling-Smee, W. Hoppitt, and T. Uller. 2012. More on how and why: Cause and effect in biology revisited. Biology & Philosophy, (in press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N.G. 2007. Nature of science: Past, present, and future. In Handbook of research on science education, ed. S.K. Abell and N.G. Lederman, 831–880. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrmann, Daniel. 1970. Semantic and conceptual issues in the nature-nurture problem. In Development and evolution of behavior, ed. R. Aronson, E. Tobach, D.S. Lehrman, and J.S. Rosenblatt, 17–52. San Francisco: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leimar, O., P. Hammerstein, and T.J.M. Van Dooren. 2006. A new perspective on developmental plasticity and the principles of adaptive morph determination. American Naturalist 167: 367–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lerner, I.M. 1950. Population genetics and animal improvement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R.C. 1983. Gene, organism, and environment. In Evolution from molecules to men, ed. D.S. Bendall, 273–285. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mameli, M. 2004. Nongenetic selection and nongenetic inheritance. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55: 35–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. 1994. Science teaching. The role of history and philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1942. Systematics and the origin of species. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1961. Cause and effect in biology. Science 134: 1501–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1982. The growth of biological thought. Diversity, evolution and inheritance. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1993. Proximate and ultimate causations. Biology and Philosophy 8: 93–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mills Shaw, K.R., K. Van Horne, H. Zhang, and J. Boughman. 2008. Essay contest reveals misconceptions of high school students in genetics content. Genetics 178: 1157–1168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mivart, St G. 1871. On the genesis of species. New York: D. Appleton & Co.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moczek, A.P. 2007. Developmental capacitance, genetic accommodation, and adaptive evolution. Evolution & Development 9: 299–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T.H. 1910. Chromosomes and heredity. American Naturalist 44: 449–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T.H., A.H. Sturtevant, H.J. Muller, and C.B. Bridges. 1915. The mechanisms of Mendelian heredity. New York: Henry Holt & Co.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille, S., and H.-J. Rheinberger. 2007. Heredity produced. At the crossroads of biology, politics, and culture, 1500–1870. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille, S., and H.-J. Rheinberger. 2012. A cultural history of heredity. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Neumann-Held, E.M., and C. Rehmann-Sutter. 2006. Genes in development. Re-reading the molecular paradigm. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newth, D.R., and M. Balls. 1979. Maternal effects in development. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nijhout, H.F. 1990. Metaphors and the role of genes in development. BioEssays 12: 441–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, F.J., K.N. Laland, and M.W. Feldman. 2003. Niche construction. The neglected process in evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. 2006. Evolution and the levels of selection. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. 1985. The ontogeny of information. Developmental systems and evolution. 2nd ed. 2000. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfennig, D.W., and R.A. Martin. 2009. A maternal effect mediates rapid population divergence and character displacement in spadefoot toads. Evolution 63: 898–909.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., and G.B. Müller. 2010. Evolution. The expanded synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, G.R. 1970. Selection and covariance. Nature 227: 520–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Provine, W.B. 1971. The origins of population genetics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riddle, O. 1909. Our knowledge of melanin color formation and its bearing on the Mendelian description of heredity. Biological Bulletin 16: 316–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, S.R., and V. Méndez-Gallardo. 2011. Amniotic fluid as an extended milieu intérieur. In Developmental science, behaviour, and genetics, ed. K.E. Hood, C.T. Halpern, G. Greenberg, and R.M. Lerner, 234–284. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenblatt, J.S. 2010. Behavioral development during the mother-young interaction in placental mammals. In Developmental science, behaviour, and genetics, ed. K.E. Hood, C.T. Halpern, G. Greenberg, and R.M. Lerner, 205–233. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sapp, J. 1987. Beyond the gene. Cytoplasmic inheritance and the struggle for authority in genetics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmalhausen, I.I. 1949. Factors of evolution. The theory of stabilizing selection. Philadelphia: Blakeston Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoener, T.W. 2011. The newest synthesis: Understanding the interplay of evolutionary and ecological dynamics. Science 331: 426–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. 2009. Imitation as an inheritance system. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 364: 2429–2443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. 2011. Developmental systems theory formulated as a claim about inherited representations. Philosophy of Science 78: 60–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. (in press). Two modes of transgenerational information transmission. In Signaling, commitment, and emotion, ed. B. Calcott et al. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N., I. Pen, and T. Uller. 2011. Three epigenetic information channels and their different roles in evolution. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 24: 1178–1187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, G.G. 1944. Tempo and mode in evolution. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. 2010. Signals. Evolution, learning and information. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J.E.H. 2006. The problem of animal generation in early modern philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M.U. 2010. Current status of research in teaching and learning evolution II: Pedagogical issues. Science and Education 19: 539–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stebbins, G.L. 1950. Variation and evolution in plants. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., K.C. Smith, and M. Dickison. 1996. The extended replicator. Biology and Philosophy 11: 377–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stubbe, H. 1972. History of genetics, from prehistoric times to the rediscovery of Mendel’s laws. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturtevant, A.H. 1913. The linear arrangement of six sex-linked factors in Drosophila, as shown by their mode of association. The Journal of Experimental Zoology 14: 43–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tal, O., E. Kisdi, and E. Jablonka. 2010. Epigenetic contribution to covariance between relatives. Genetics 184: 1037–1050.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uller, T. 2008. Developmental plasticity and the evolution of parental effects. Trends in Ecology & Evolution 23: 432–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uller, T. 2012. Parental effects in development and evolution. In Evolution of parental care, ed. N. Royle, P. Smiseth, and M. Kölliker, 247–266. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uller, T., and H. Helanterä. 2011. From the origin of sex-determining factors to the evolution of sex-determining systems. The Quarterly Review of Biology 86: 163–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uller, T., and I. Pen. 2011. A theoretical model of the evolution of maternal effects under parent-­offspring conflict. Evolution 65: 2075–2084.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C.H. 1942. Canalization of development and the inheritance of acquired characters. Nature 150: 563–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warner, D.A. 2011. Sex determination in reptiles. In Hormones and reproduction of vertebrates, volume 3: Reptiles, ed. D.O. Norris and K. Lopez, 1–38. Amsterdam: Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 1994. Genes made molecular. Philosophy of Science 61(2): 163–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, P.D., M.C. Wallis, and J.A.M. Graves. 2007. Mammalian sex – Origin and evolution of the Y chromosome and SRY. Seminars in Cell & Developmental Biology 18: 389–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weismann, A. 1893. The germ-plasm. A theory of heredity. London: Walter Scott.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, S.A. 2009. Sex allocation. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M.J. 2003. Developmental plasticity and evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M.J. 2005. Phenotypic accommodation: Adaptive innovation due to developmental plasticity. Journal of Experimental Zoology. Part B, Molecular and Developmental Evolution 304B: 610–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G.C. 1966. Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Kostas Kampourakis for the invitation to contribute to this volume and Sinead English, Heikki Helanterä, Kostas Kampourakis, Eva Jablonka, and Nick Shea for comments on the chapter. My work on non-genetic inheritance is funded in part by the European Union’s Seventh Framework Programme (FP7/2007-2011) under grant agreement n° 259679.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tobias Uller .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Uller, T. (2013). Non-genetic Inheritance and Evolution. In: Kampourakis, K. (eds) The Philosophy of Biology. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6537-5_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics