Skip to main content

Teaching Evolutionary Developmental Biology: Concepts, Problems, and Controversy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Philosophy of Biology

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 1))

Abstract

Although sciences are often conceptualized in terms of theory confirmation and hypothesis testing, an equally important dimension of scientific reasoning is the structure of problems that guide inquiry. This problem structure is evident in several concepts central to evolutionary developmental biology (Evo-devo)—constraints, modularity, evolvability, and novelty. Because problems play an important role in biological practice, they should be included in biological pedagogy, especially when treating the issue of scientific controversy. A key feature of resolving controversy is synthesizing methodologies from different biological disciplines to generate empirically adequate explanations. Concentrating on problem structure illuminates this interdisciplinarity in a way that is often ignored when science is taught only from the perspective of theory or hypothesis. These philosophical considerations can assist life science educators in their continuing quest to teach biology to the next generation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Theories or hypotheses are assumed to guide inquiry: “Hypotheses are widely used in science for choosing what data to pay attention to and what additional data to seek” (AAAS 2009, ch. 1).

  2. 2.

    “Pertaining to questioning”: derived from the Greek noun erotisis, which means “a question.”

  3. 3.

    Claims of a recent, developmental genetic genesis for Evo-devo should be treated suspiciously. For example, “Evo-devo began in the pre-genomic era when genetic studies in Drosophila and gene cloning in Xenopus revealed that the Hox genes that control the anterior-posterior (A-P) axis were unexpectedly conserved” (De Robertis 2008, p. 186).

  4. 4.

    These adult phenotypes were primarily exemplified in multicellular animals (metazoans), as well as some plants. Microbial phenotypes, whether morphological or behavioral, were largely neglected (see Duncan et al. this volume).

  5. 5.

    “Theories compete for acceptance;” science is construed as “the testing, revising, and occasional discarding of theories” (AAAS 2009, ch. 1).

  6. 6.

    The terminology of constraints connotes negativity or prevention but developmental constraints sometimes provide positive evolutionary opportunities (Gould 2002). As a result, some authors prefer “bias” as a more general designator, with “constraints” being one species of the genus (Arthur 2004). Here I do not distinguish between these different connotations and use constraint and bias interchangeably.

  7. 7.

    Others properties underlying evolvability include the versatility of cell components, weak regulatory linkages, and exploratory behavior (see Kirschner and Gerhart 2005).

  8. 8.

    Other controversies that might have been explored include disagreements about whether most molecular change during evolution occurs in cis-regulatory regions of the genome that control gene expression or within protein coding regions of the genome (see Hoekstra and Coyne 2007).

  9. 9.

    Thus, ‘Mendelian’ refers to standard transmission and developmental genetic processes we find in contemporary organisms. ‘Pre-Mendelian’ signifies that these standard processes were not yet in place even though phenotypes were being generated through environmental forces interacting with soft condensed materials according to physical principles.

  10. 10.

    Differences (‘hetero’) in development that contribute to evolutionary change can be classified according to the kind of difference in view: (i) heterochrony: differences in the timing of developmental events; (ii) heterotopy: differences in the spatial location of developmental events; (iii) heterotypy: differences in the type of developmental event, such as cavitation versus invagination; and, (iv) heterometry: differences in the amount of activity in developmental events, such as the up-regulation of gene expression (Arthur 2002).

  11. 11.

    “The current preeminence of the molecular genetic approach to biology, in which living systems are conceptualized as networks of interacting genes and proteins, may have obscured this inevitable link between physics and biology in the mind of scientists” (Mulder 2008, p. 1643); “there has been a renewed appreciation of the fact that to understand morphogenesis in three dimensions, it is necessary to combine molecular insights (genes and morphogens) with knowledge of physical processes (transport, deformation and flow) generated by growing tissues” (Savin et al. 2011, p. 57).

  12. 12.

    Uniformitarianism is a stronger principle that actualism. The former combines actualism and a commitment to extant causes operating with the same intensity throughout history.

  13. 13.

    This conception, minus the metaphorical pachyderm, is present in the NSES: “The natural […] world is complex; it is too large and complicated to investigate and comprehend all at once. Students and scientists learn to define small portions for the convenience of investigation” (p. 116).

References

  • AAAS. 2009. Benchmarks for scientific literacy. AAAS Project 2061. New York: Oxford University Press. http://www.project2061.org/publications/bsl/online/.

  • Alberch, P., and E.A. Gale. 1985. A developmental analysis of an evolutionary trend: Digital reduction in amphibians. Evolution 39: 8–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. 2003. Lawson’s shoehorn, or should the philosophy of science be rated “X”? Science & Education 12: 315–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. 2011. Evaluating knowledge of the nature of (whole) science. Science & Education 95(3): 518–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. 1994. Two concepts of constraint: Adaptationism and the challenge from developmental biology. Philosophy of Science 61: 556–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. 2005. The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought: Roots of Evo-Devo. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, W. 2002. The emerging conceptual framework of evolutionary developmental biology. Nature 415: 757–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, W. 2004. Biased embryos and evolution. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, W. 2011. Evolution: A developmental approach. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, P., and P. Gluckman. 2011. Plasticity, robustness, development and evolution. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bolker, J.A. 2000. Modularity in development and why it matters to Evo-devo. American Zoologist 40: 770–776.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. 2010. Beyond reduction and pluralism: Toward an epistemology of explanatory integration in biology. Erkenntnis 73: 295–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I., and A.C. Love. 2010. Evolutionary novelty and the Evo-devo synthesis: Field notes. Evolutionary Biology 37: 93–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I., and A.C. Love, 2012a. Reductionism in biology. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reduction-biology/

  • Brigandt, I., and A.C. Love. 2012b. Conceptualizing evolutionary novelty: Moving beyond definitional debates. Journal of Experimental Zoology. Part B, Molecular and Developmental Evolution 318: 417–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, S.B. 2005. Endless forms most beautiful: The new science of Evo-devo. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, E.H. 2006. The regulatory genome: Gene regulatory networks in development and evolution. San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Robertis, E.M. 2008. Evo-devo: Variations on ancestral themes. Cell 132: 185–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, S. 2002. Biological science. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerhart, J., and M. Kirschner. 2007. The theory of facilitated variation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 104: 8582–8589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S.F. 2003. Opening Darwin’s black box: Teaching evolution through developmental genetics. Nature Reviews Genetics 4: 735–741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gompel, N., B. Prud’homme, P.J. Wittkopp, V.A. Kassner, and S.B. Carroll. 2005. Chance caught on the wing: Cis-regulatory evolution and the origin of pigment patterns in Drosophila. Nature 433: 481–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 2002. The structure of evolutionary theory. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hattiangadi, J.N. 1978. The structure of problems, part I. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 8: 345–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hattiangadi, J.N. 1979. The structure of problems, part II. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 9: 49–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendrikse, J.L., T.E. Parsons, and B. Hallgrímmson. 2007. Evolvability as the proper focus of evolutionary developmental biology. Evolution & Development 9: 393–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoekstra, H.E., and J.A. Coyne. 2007. The locus of evolution: Evo-devo and the genetics of adaptation. Evolution 61: 995–1016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holton, Martha Adelaide, and Charles Madison Curry. 1914. Blind men and an elephant. In Holton-Curry readers, 108. Chicago: Rand McNally & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, M., and J. Gerhart. 1998. Evolvability. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 95: 8420–8427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, M.W., and J.C. Gerhart. 2005. The plausibility of life: Resolving Darwin’s dilemma. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuratani, S. 2009. Modularity, comparative embryology and evo-devo: Developmental dissection of evolving body plans. Developmental Biology 332: 61–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler, M.D. 2009. Form and function in Evo devo: Historical and conceptual reflections. In Form and function in developmental evolution, ed. M.D. Laubichler and J. Maienschein, 10–46. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler, M.D. 2010. Evolutionary developmental biology offers a significant challenge to the neo-Darwinian paradigm. In Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology, ed. F.J. Ayala and R. Arp, 199–212. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. 1977. Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, A. 2003. Allchin’s shoehorn, or why science is hypothetico-deductive. Science & Education 12: 331–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C. 2003. Evolutionary morphology, innovation, and the synthesis of evolutionary and developmental biology. Biology and Philosophy 18: 309–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C. 2007. Morphological and paleontological perspectives for a history of Evo-devo. In From embryology to Evo-devo: A history of developmental evolution, ed. M. Laubichler and J. Maienschein, 267–307. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C. 2008a. Explaining evolutionary innovation and novelty: Criteria of explanatory adequacy and epistemological prerequisites. Philosophy of Science 75: 874–886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C. 2008b. From philosophy to science (to natural philosophy): Evolutionary developmental perspectives. The Quarterly Review of Biology 83: 65–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C. 2009. Marine invertebrates, model organisms, and the modern synthesis: Epistemic values, evo-devo, and exclusion. Theory in Biosciences 128: 19–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C. 2013a. Interdisciplinary lessons for the teaching of biology from the practice of Evo-devo. Science & Education 22(2): 255–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C. 2013b. Theory is as theory does: Scientific practice and theory structure in biology. Biological Theory. doi:10.1007/s13752-012-0046-2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C., and R.A. Raff. 2003. Knowing your ancestors: Themes in the history of Evo-devo. Evolution & Development 5: 327–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. 2007. The frailty of adaptive hypotheses for the origins of organismal complexity. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 104: 8597–8604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., R. Burian, S. Kauffman, P. Alberch, J. Campbell, B. Goodwin, R. Lande, D. Raup, and L. Wolpert. 1985. Developmental constraints and evolution. The Quarterly Review of Biology 60: 265–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayo, D. 1996. Error and the growth of experimental knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Metscher, B.D., and P.E. Ahlberg. 1999. Zebrafish in context: Uses of a laboratory model in comparative studies. Developmental Biology 210: 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Minelli, A. 2009. Forms of becoming: The evolutionary biology of development. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minelli, A. 2010. Evolutionary developmental biology does not offer a significant challenge to the neo-Darwinian paradigm. In Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology, ed. F.J. Ayala and R. Arp, 213–226. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulder, B. 2008. On growth and force. Science 322: 1643–1644.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G.B. 2007. Evo-devo: Extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nature Reviews Genetics 8: 943–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G.B., and S.A. Newman. 2005. The innovation triad: An EvoDevo agenda. Journal of Experimental Zoology. Part B, Molecular and Developmental Evolution 304B: 487–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S.A. 1994. Generic physical mechanisms of tissue morphogenesis: A common basis for development and evolution. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 7: 467–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S.A., and R. Bhat. 2009. Dynamical patterning modules: A “pattern language” for development and evolution of multicellular form. International Journal of Developmental Biology 53: 693–705.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S.A., G. Forgacs, and G.B. Müller. 2006. Before programs: The physical origination of multicellular forms. International Journal of Developmental Biology 50: 289–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. 1981. What is a problem that we may solve it? Synthese 47: 85–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • NRC. 1996. National science education standards. Washington, DC: National Academy Press (National Research Council).

    Google Scholar 

  • NRC, 2008. The role of theory in advancing 21st-century biology: Catalyzing transformative research. Washington, DC: Committee on Defining and Advancing the Conceptual Basis of Biological Sciences in the 21st Century: National Research Council, National Academies of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osbeck, L.M., N.J. Nersessian, K.R. Malone, and W.C. Newstetter. 2011. Science as psychology: Sense-making and identity in science practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. 2002 [1963]. Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prum, R.O., and A.H. Brush. 2002. The evolutionary origin and diversification of feathers. The Quarterly Review of Biology 77: 261–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raff, R.A. 2000. Evo-Devo: The evolution of a new discipline. Nature Reviews Genetics 1: 74–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raff, R.A. 2007. Written in stone: Fossils, genes, and evo-devo. Nature Reviews Genetics 8: 911–920.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raff, R.A. 2008. Origins of the other metazoan body plans: The evolution of larval forms. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences 363: 1473–1479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raff, E.C., E.M. Popodi, J.S. Kauffman, B.J. Sly, F.R. Turner, V.B. Morris, and R.A. Raff. 2003. Regulatory punctuated equilibrium and convergence in the evolution of developmental pathways in direct-developing sea urchins. Evolution & Development 5: 478–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. 2007. Doubting Darwin? Creationist designs on evolution. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savin, T., N.A. Kurpios, A.E. Shyer, P. Florescu, H. Liang, L. Mahadevan, and C. Tabin. 2011. On the growth and form of the gut. Nature 476: 57–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, E.C., and G. Branch. 2003. Evolution: What’s wrong with ‘teaching the controversy’. Trends in Ecology & Evolution 18: 499–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shubin, N.H. 2008. Your inner fish: A journey into the 3.5-billion-year history of the human body. New York: Vintage Books (Random House).

    Google Scholar 

  • Shubin, N., C. Tabin, and S. Carroll. 2009. Deep homology and the origins of evolutionary novelty. Nature 457: 818–823.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stearns, S.C. 1992. The evolution of life histories. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, D.L. 2011. Evolution, development, and the predictable genome. Greenwood Village: Roberts and Company Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Telford, M.J., and G.E. Budd. 2003. The place of phylogeny and cladistics in Evo-Devo research. International Journal of Developmental Biology 47: 479–490.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G.P. 2000. What is the promise of developmental evolution? Part I: Why is developmental biology necessary to explain evolutionary innovations? Journal of Experimental Zoology. Part B, Molecular and Developmental Evolution 288: 95–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G.P., and V.J. Lynch. 2010. Evolutionary novelties. Current Biology 20: R48–R52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G., and J. Zhang. 2011. The pleiotropic structure of the genotype-phenotype map: The evolvability of complex organisms. Nature Reviews Genetics 12: 204–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G.P., C.-H. Chiu, and M. Laubichler. 2000. Developmental evolution as a mechanistic science: The inference from developmental mechanisms to evolutionary processes. American Zoologist 40: 819–831.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Kostas Kampourakis for the invitation to contribute this chapter. Many of the ideas set forth here emerged in collaboration with my colleague Ingo Brigandt and I acknowledge my debt to him in working out details related to a problem-oriented conception of scientific inquiry. Wallace Arthur and Kostas Kampourakis provided helpful comments and critical feedback on an earlier version of the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alan C. Love .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Love, A.C. (2013). Teaching Evolutionary Developmental Biology: Concepts, Problems, and Controversy. In: Kampourakis, K. (eds) The Philosophy of Biology. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6537-5_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics