Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 34))

Abstract

The detailed investigation of intentionality stands as a major achievement in 20th Century philosophy. This focus upon the ability of subjectivity to be directed toward and occupied with objects different from itself should, however, not obscure the fact that it has another important, but apparently antithetical feature, namely self-awareness. Obviously I can be aware of blooming trees, rainy mornings or the cries of playing children, but I can also be aware that these are seen, smelled and heard, that different perceptions are taking place, and that I am the one experiencing them, just as I might be aware that I am hungry, tired or happy.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Let me emphasize that it is not only legitimate to speak of self-awareness when I realize that / am perceiving a candle, but also when I am aware of my feeling of sorrow, or my burning pain, or my perception of a candle, that is, whenever I am acquainted with an experience in its first-personal mode of givenness. I am entitled to speak of self-awareness the moment I am no longer simply conscious of a foreign object, but of my experience of the object as well, for in this case my subjectivity reveals itself to me.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. M. Frank, Was ist Neostrukturalismus? (Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, 1984);

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. M. Frank, Die Unhintergehbarkeit von Individualität (Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, 1986);

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cf. M. Frank, Das Sagbare und das Unsagbare (Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, 1989);

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. M. Frank, Zeitbewußtsein (Pfullingen: Neske, 1990);

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. M. Frank, Selbstbewußtsein und Selbsterkenntnis (Stuttgart: Reclam, 1991a);

    Google Scholar 

  7. Cf. M. Frank, Selbstbewußtseinstheorien von Fichte bis Sartre (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1991b).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Frank 1984, 357.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Frank 1991b, 428, 529.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cf. D. Henrich, “Fichtes ursprüngliche Einsicht” in D. Henrich & H. Wagner (eds): Subjektivität und Metaphysik. Festschrift für Wolf gang Cramer (Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 1966), 188–232;

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. D. Henrich, “Selbstbewußtsein, kritische Einleitung in eine Theorie” in Bubner, Cramer, Wiehl (eds.): Hermeneutik und Dialektik (Tübingen, 1970), 257–284;

    Google Scholar 

  12. K. Cramer, “‘Erlebnis.’ Thesen zu Hegels Theorie des Selbstbewußtseins mit Rücksicht auf die Aporien eines Grundbegriffs nachhegelscher Philosophie,” in H.-G. Gadamer (ed.): Stuttgarter Hegel-Tage 1970 (Bonn, 1974), 537–603;

    Google Scholar 

  13. U. Pothast, Über einige Fragen der Selbstbeziehung (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Frank 1986, 34, 61, Frank 1991a, 71, 405, Frank 1991b, 597. Actually Frank explicitly denies that self-awareness is a “présence à soi” since he takes this expression to designate a kind of self-presentification which is completely indebted to the reflection model (Frank 1989, 488, 1991a, 24). However, it seems difficult to find a more perfect candidate for a pure unmediated self-presence than the completely irrelational self-acquaintance described by Frank, which is so close to itself that every kind of mediation is excluded.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Frank 1991a, 7, 161, Frank 1991b, 438.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf. Henrich 1966, 231, Henrich 1970, 261; Frank 1986, 44–45, 50, Frank 1991b, 530, 536, 557, 562; Cramer 1974, 584, 590, 592.

    Google Scholar 

  17. M. Henry, L’essence de la manifestation (Paris: P.U.F., 1963);

    Google Scholar 

  18. M. Henry, Philosophie et phénoménologie du corps (Paris: P.U.F., 1965);

    Google Scholar 

  19. M. Henry, “Le concept d’âme a-t-il un sens?” Revue philosophique de Louvain 64 (1966), 5–33;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. M. Henry, “Philosophie et subjectivité,” in Jacob (ed.): Encyclopédie philosophique universelle, Bd.L: L’univers philosophique (Paris: P.U.F., 1989), 46–56;

    Google Scholar 

  21. M. Henry, Phénoménologie matérielle (Paris: P.U.F., 1990);

    Google Scholar 

  22. M. Henry, “Phénoménologie de la naissance” Alter 2 (1994), 295–312;

    Google Scholar 

  23. M. Henry, C’est moi la vérité (Paris: Seuil, 1996).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Henry 1989, 50.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Henry 1963, 14, 32, 64, 67, Henry 1966, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Henry 1963, 36, 50.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Henry 1963, 44, 279, 329, 352, Henry 1966, 22–23.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Henry 1963, 47, 52, 168–169, 173.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Henry 1963, 288–292, 301.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Henry 1963, 578, 580, 590.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Henry 1963, 576, 349, 858.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Henry 1990, 166, Henry 1966, 33, Henry 1965, 139.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Henry 1990, 33–34. Cf. Hua X, 89, 110–111, 119, XI, 337. Page references are to the Husserliana edition. When referring to Husserl’s unpublished manuscripts the last number always refers to the original page in shorthand.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Henry 1990, 32.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Henry 1990, 49–50.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Henry 1990, 107.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Henry 1990, 130.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Cf. F.-D. Sebbah, “Aux limites de Pintentionnalité: M. Henry et E. Lévinas lecteurs des Leçons sur la conscience intime du temps” Alter 2 (1994), 252.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Henry 1994, 303–304, 310, Henry 1996, 201–202.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Henry 1990, 72, Henry 1963, 279–280, 351, 352, 377, 419.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Henry 1963, 58, 396, Henry 1990, 111.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Henry 1990, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Henry 1963, 477.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Henry 1963, 53, 480–482, 490, 549, Henry 1990, 125, 164.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Henry 1963, 53, 57, 550, 555.

    Google Scholar 

  46. This title evokes Heidegger’s remark in Sein und Zeit concerning the necessity of analyzing the phenomena which remain hidden from view, and when he says that it is exactly Being which is the most concealed (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer, 1986), 35. Cf. J.-L. Marion, Réduction et donation (Paris: P.U.F., 1989), 90–97.

    Google Scholar 

  47. I am not implying that alterity, difference and fracture are all one and the same. But each of these notions constitutes problems for Frank’s and Henry’s theories.

    Google Scholar 

  48. J. Derrida, La voix et le phénomène (Paris: P.U.F., 1967a);

    Google Scholar 

  49. J. Derrida, De la grammatologie (Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit, 1967c);

    Google Scholar 

  50. E. Husserl, Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973);

    Google Scholar 

  51. E. Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie II (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1952);

    Google Scholar 

  52. E. Husserl, Erste Philosophie II (1923–24) (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1959);

    Google Scholar 

  53. E. Husserl, Phänomenologische Psychologie (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1962);

    Google Scholar 

  54. E. Husserl, Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewußtseins (1893–1917) (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1966);

    Google Scholar 

  55. E. Husserl, Analysen zur passiven Synthesis (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1966);

    Google Scholar 

  56. E. Husserl, Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität I (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973);

    Book  Google Scholar 

  57. E. Husserl, Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität II (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973);

    Book  Google Scholar 

  58. E. Husserl, Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität III (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973);

    Book  Google Scholar 

  59. E. Husserl, Erfahrung und Urteil (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  60. M. Merleau-Ponty, Phénoménologie de la perception (Paris: Éditions Gallimard, 1945);

    Google Scholar 

  61. M. Merleau-Ponty, Signes (Paris: Éditions Gallimard, 1960a);

    Google Scholar 

  62. M. Merleau-Ponty, Les relations avec autrui chez l’enfant (Paris: Centre de Documentation Universitaire, 1960b);

    Google Scholar 

  63. M. Merleau-Ponty, Le visible et l’invisible (Paris: Tel Gallimard, 1964);

    Google Scholar 

  64. M. Merleau-Ponty, Sens et non-sens (Paris: Les Éditions Nagel, 1966);

    Google Scholar 

  65. M. Merleau-Ponty, La prose du monde (Paris: Tel Gallimard, 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  66. J.-P. Sartre, “Conscience de soi et connaissance de soi.” Bulletin Soc. Franc, de Philosophie XLII (1948), 49–91;

    Google Scholar 

  67. J.-P. Sartre, La transcendance de l’ego (Paris: J. Vrin, 1936/1988);

    Google Scholar 

  68. J.-P. Sartre, L’être et le néant (Paris: Tel Gallimard, 1943/1976).

    Google Scholar 

  69. Merleau-Ponty 1945, 431–432, 485, 487, 492, Merleau-Ponty 1966, 164–165. Cf. Sartre 1943, 212, Sartre 1936, 23–24.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Hua XV, 128, 375, XIII, 406, 459, XIV, 51–52, 337, IV, 356, Ms. E III 2 5a, Ms. E III 2 23a. I thank the director of the Husserl-Archives in Louvain, Belgium, Professor R. Bernet, for permission to quote from Husserl’s unpublished manuscripts.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Ms. E III 2 22a. Cf. Ms. C 6 4b. Of course, it remains necessary to distinguish the alterity of the hyletic material from the alterity of the Other, and it is important to counter the suggestion that we are simply dealing with two different types or manifestations of one and the same alterity. But in the present context, this separate problem can be put aside.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Hua XIV, 379.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Hua XIV, 14. Needless to say, this should not be interpreted in a realistic vein. That which I am affected by is different from me, but it is not ontologically independent of me. Quite to the contrary: When Husserl says that the hyle as the core of interpretations, sense-formations, feelings and drives is inseparable from the ego, he is also saying that the hyle has no place outside of subjectivity. Nevertheless the hyle remains foreign. It is a domain in me which escapes my control, since it is pre-given without any active participation or contribution by the ego (Hua XIII, 427, XI 386). Husserl speaks of an interior non-egological dimension, which surrounds and affects the ego (Ms. E IE 2 22b). It is an immanent type of alterity which manifests itself directly in subjectivity, which belongs intrinsically to subjectivity, and which subjectivity cannot do without. Both are, as Husserl says, inseparable, both are irreducible structural moments in the process of constitution, in the process of bringing to appearance. For a more detailed analysis of this aspect of Husserl’s philosophy see D. Zahavi, “Self-awareness and affection” in Depraz and Zahavi (eds.): Alterity and Facticity. New Perspectives on Husserl (Dordrect: Kluwer, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  74. Hua XIV, 245. Cf. Hua XIII, 92, 170, XIV, 51.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Huai, 28, Ms. LI 15 3a, Husserl 1985, 76.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Hua XI, 137, Ms. A V 5 7a, Ms. L 117 9b, Ms. C 3 42a.

    Google Scholar 

  77. E. Lévinas, En découvrant l’existence avec Husserl et Heidegger (Paris: Vrin, 1949), 154.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Hua X, 107.

    Google Scholar 

  79. HuaX, 80, 83, 117–118.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Hua IV, 58, Xm, 386.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Hua IV, 147.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Hua XIV, 75, XV, 297, 301.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Hua XIV, 75, Ms. D 12 III 14, 19.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Hua XV, 300, XIV, 457, 462, IX, 197, Xffl, 263. According to Husserl, it is this double-appearance of the body, this remarkable interplay between ipseity and alterity characterizing our bodily self-awareness, which enables us to recognize embodied Others as other subjects (HuaVIII, 62).

    Google Scholar 

  85. J. Benoist, Autour de Husserl (Paris: Vrin, 1994), 57, 61;

    Google Scholar 

  86. R. Bernet, La vie du sujet (Paris: P.U.F., 1994), 321;

    Google Scholar 

  87. P. Ricoeur, Soi-même comme un autre (Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1990), 380.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Ms. C 16 68a. Cf. Ms. C 10 2b.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Sartre 1943, 212, 1936, 23–24.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Sartre 1943, 28.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Sartre 1943, 162.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Sartre 1943, 27, 214–215.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Sartre 1943, 179. Cf. Sartre 1943, 213, 258 and Sartre 1936, 28.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Sartre 1943, 178.

    Google Scholar 

  95. J. Rosenberg, “Apperception and Sartre’s Pre-Reflective Cogito,” American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1981), 257.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Sartre 1943, 115.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Sartre 1943, 115–116.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Sartre 1943, 33.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Sartre 1943, 115–116. Cf. Merleau-Ponty 1964, 246.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Sartre 1943, 114, 117, Sartre 1947, 67. On the pre-reflective level consciousness is characterized by the dyad reflet-reflétant, on the reflective level by the duality réflexif-réfléchif.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Sartre 1943, 116, 141, 144, 175–177, 182, 197, 245, Sartre 1948, 76. Despite his emphasis on time, and despite taking the dyadic structure of pre-reflective self-awareness to constitute the origin of temporality, Sartre nevertheless conceived of the structure itself as being atemporal.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Merleau-Ponty 1945, 427–428.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Merleau-Ponty 1945, 405. Cf. Merleau-Ponty 1945, 402.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Merleau-Ponty 1945, 400–401, 405, 511.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Hua 1, 128.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Derrida 1967a, 88, Bernet 1994, 173.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Merleau-Ponty 1945, 406, Merleau-Ponty 1960a, 213, 215, 221, Merleau-Ponty 1960b, 35, Merleau-Ponty 1964, 74, 278, Merleau-Ponty 1969, 186, 188.

    Google Scholar 

  108. G. Brand, Welt, Ich und Zeit (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1955), 74.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  109. Cf. T. Seebohm, Die Bedingungen der Möglichkeit der Tranzendental-Philosophie (Bouvier, 1962), 126–127);

    Google Scholar 

  110. J.G. Hart, “Constitution and reference in Husserl’s phenomenology of phenomenology,” Husserl Studies 6 (1989), 58;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  111. K. Held, “Phänomenologie der Zeit nach Husserl” Perspektiven der Philosophie 1 (1981), 192.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Derrida 1967a, 89, 92.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Derrida 1967c, 235.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Derrida 1967a, 92, Derrida 1967c, 221, 237.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Cf. R. Barbaras, “Le sens de l’auto-affection chez Michel Henry et Merleau-Ponty,” Epokhè 2 (1991) 107.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Y. Yamagata, “Une autre lecture de L’essence de la manifestation: immanence, présent vivant et altérité” Études philosophiques 2 (1991), 179.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Hua XV, 349.

    Google Scholar 

  118. R. Sokolowski, “Ontological Possibilities in Phenomenology: The Dyad and the One,” Review of Metaphysics XXDC (1976), 699;

    Google Scholar 

  119. J.B. Brough, “The Emergence of an Absolute Consciousness in Husserl’s Early Writings on Time-Consciousness,” Man and World 5 (1972), 326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  120. Sartre 1948, 63. 81.Derridal967a, 76.

    Google Scholar 

  121. It is interesting to note that Henry takes the distinction between the reflective and the pre-reflective cogito to be equivocal, and he himself does not use the term “pre-reflective” as a designation of the originary self-manifestation (Henry 1965, 76). Presumably, this is because the notion betrays a certain affiliation with the paradigm of reflection. To designate self-awareness as pre-reflective indicates that reflective self-awareness is still the yardstick.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Sartre 1943, 113, 194.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Ms. C 3 69a.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Hua XV, 543–544.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Held 1981, 192.

    Google Scholar 

  126. For a large-scale analysis of the structure of pre-reflective self-awareness see my Self-awareness andAlterity (forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Zahavi, D. (1998). The Fracture in Self-Awareness. In: Zahavi, D. (eds) Self-Awareness, Temporality, and Alterity. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 34. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9078-5_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9078-5_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5031-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9078-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics