Skip to main content

Generalizing Mechanistic Explanations Using Graph-Theoretic Representations

  • Chapter
Explanation in Biology

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 11))

Abstract

Mechanistic explanations appeal to the parts, operations, and organizations of mechanisms to explain the phenomena for which they are responsible. Scientists have developed accounts of myriads of mechanisms thought to be operative in biology, each involving distinctive parts and operations organized in idiosyncratic ways. The focus on specific mechanisms (e.g., those found in a particular cell type in a given model organism) appears opposed to the idea that explanations ought to be generalizable to new instances. Some generalizability can arise from the fact that many biological mechanisms inherit their parts and operations from mechanisms found in ancestral species and one can often identify commonalities in these parts and the operations they perform. But organization seems to be idiosyncratic to specific mechanisms, thwarting attempts to develop generalizations about how mechanisms organized in a specific way will behave. For example, as a result of different genes being expressed, the organizational pattern of interactions between proteins varies in different tissues or in the same tissue in different strains of a species. This poses an even greater problem when it is recognized that many biological mechanisms exhibit non-sequential organization of non-linear operations, making it difficult to use mental simulation to determine the behavior of the mechanism. Instead researchers resort to computational models, resulting in dynamic mechanistic explanations that integrate mathematical modeling with empirically ascertained details of parts and operations. These models, though, appear to be even more idiosyncratic, revealing only the behavior of the specific organization employed in a specific mechanism.

In recent years, however powerful tools have been developed for abstracting from the details of individual networks, providing a basis for informative generalizations about how networks employing the same abstract design will behave. These involve developing graph-theoretic representations of mechanisms and analyzing the properties of classes of graphs. Watts and Strogatz, Barabási, and Sporns have shown that large networks (e.g., neural circuits or gene networks) often exhibit a scale-free, small-world organization capable of efficient, flexible coordination of operations and appeal to these properties to explain behaviors of specific mechanisms. Alon and Tyson, focusing on sub-networks with just two to four nodes, have identified different motifs (distinctive micro-architectures such as feedforward loops and double negative feedback loops) that are specialized for particular types of processing. These tools offer abstract organizational principles to which researchers appeal in their efforts to explain the behaviors generated by the mechanisms in which they are implemented. In this paper I show how these projects provide a basis for developing generalizable accounts of complex mechanisms and their dynamical behavior.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Théry (2015, this volume) for a critical assessment of mechanistic explanations. See also Baetu (2015, this volume) and Brigandt (2013) about how mathematical models and mechanistic explanations may mutually support each other.

  2. 2.

    While recognizing that one might integrate them, Woodward (2013) emphasizes the differences between more prototypical mechanistic approaches and those that adopt a more holistic perspective in, for example, explaining the robustness of a biological system or the dynamical behavior of a complex network. Woodward is right to emphasize the difference in research strategies and assumptions of the two approaches. More traditional mechanistic approaches assume modularity of the mechanism and dependence on the fine-tuned details of the system. In developing dynamical models of integrated systems researchers typically abstract away from these details. My reason for emphasizing their integration in dynamic mechanistic explanations is that many contemporary biological explanations draw on both details about the components of the mechanism and the dynamics of the integrated system, attempting to integrate the approaches that on their own make different assumptions and pursue different research strategies.

  3. 3.

    See Issad and Malaterre (2015, this volume) for a discussion of the explanatory force of dynamic mechanistic explanations.

  4. 4.

    Jones (2014) discusses graph representations of the topology of a system that are not intended to be mechanistic but to identify such things as vulnerabilities of a system to disruption. While the diagrams he discusses and those discussed below often abstract from the details of the mechanism and thus provide a different type of understanding than do accounts of the parts and operations of a mechanism, they nonetheless play an important role in understanding how, as a result of its organization, a mechanism behaves either normally or when disrupted.

  5. 5.

    A special case on which extensive research has been conducted are Boolean networks (networks in which the behavior of a node is a Boolean function of the state of other nodes). See Derrida and Pomeau (1986), Flyvbjerg (1988), Kauffman (1993), Luque and Solé (1997), Rohlf and Bornholdt (2002) for analyses of Boolean networks.

  6. 6.

    The one type of task that yields comparable activation in these regions are episodic memory tasks, resulting in the suggestion that while resting quietly in the scanning individuals are remembering events in their lives or planning future events (see Buckner et al. 2008).

  7. 7.

    See also Braillard (2015, this volume) for a discussion of the heuristic and explanatory role of such motifs and more generally of modules in biology.

  8. 8.

    In his analysis of the neural network in C. elegans that he helped identify (discussed above), White (1985) identified the frequent occurrence of the feedforward loop and considered the case in which the connection from Y to Z was inhibitory. He proposed X would initially elicit a response from Z, but this would be soon be suppressed as a result of the negative connection from Y to Z. He suggests: “The whole system would therefore act as a differentiator, the output from [Z] being proportional to the rate of change of stimulus. As the animal is constantly moving, this reformation is probably of more value to it than an absolute measure of the stimulus.”

  9. 9.

    They report that computational analyses show that dual dyads are particularly effective in promoting zero phase-lag synchrony over long distances, which is important if hubs are to coordinate synchronous activity between brain regions.

  10. 10.

    Ward and Thornton (2007) propose a possible origin of feedforward loops from another motif the authors term the bi-fan array to genome-wide duplication followed by random rewiring. This provides an explanation for their occurrence that doesn’t depend on selection, although Ward and Thornton do not deny that selection may have also favored these motifs.

References

  • Alon, U. (2007a). An introduction to systems biology: Design principles of biological circuits. Boca Raton: Chapman & Hall/CRC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alon, U. (2007b). Network motifs: Theory and experimental approaches. Nature Reviews Genetics, 8, 450–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny, R. A. (2001). Model organisms as models: Understanding the ‘Lingua Franca’ of the human genome project. Philosophy of Science, 68, S251–S261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny, R. A., & Leonelli, S. (2011). What’s so special about model organisms? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42, 313–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Artzy-Randrup, Y., Fleishman, S. J., Ben-Tal, N., & Stone, L. (2004). Comment on ‘network motifs: Simple building blocks of complex networks’ and ‘superfamilies of evolved and designed networks’. Science, 305, 1107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baetu, T. (2015). From mechanisms to mathematical models and back to mechanisms: Quantitative mechanistic explanations. In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 345–363). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barabási, A.-L., & Albert, R. (1999). Emergence of scaling in random networks. Science, 286, 509–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2011). Mechanism and biological explanation. Philosophy of Science, 78, 533–557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2009). Decomposing, recomposing, and situating circadian mechanisms: Three tasks in developing mechanistic explanations. In H. Leitgeb & A. Hieke (Eds.), Reduction and elimination in philosophy of mind and philosophy of neuroscience (pp. 173–186). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2010). Dynamic mechanistic explanation: Computational modeling of circadian rhythms as an exemplar for cognitive science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41, 321–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2011). Complex biological mechanisms: Cyclic, oscillatory, and autonomous. In C. A. Hooker (Ed.), Philosophy of complex systems. Handbook of the philosophy of science (Vol. 10, pp. 257–285). New York: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993/2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 1993 edition published by Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg, H. C. (2004). E. coli in motion. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Biswal, B., Yetkin, F. Z., Haughton, V. M., & Hyde, J. S. (1995). Functional connectivity in the motor cortex of resting human brain using echo-planar MRI. Magnetic Resonance in Medicine, 34, 537–541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braillard, P.-A. (2015). Prospect and limits of explaining biological systems in engineering terms. In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 319–344). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2013). Systems biology and the integration of mechanistic explanation and mathematical explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 477–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, R. L., Andrews-Hanna, J. R., & Schacter, D. L. (2008). The brain’s default network: Anatomy, function, and relevance to disease. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1124, 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bullmore, E., & Sporns, O. (2009). Complex brain networks: Graph theoretical analysis of structural and functional systems. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10, 186–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordes, D., Haughton, V. M., Arfanakis, K., Wendt, G. J., Turski, P. A., Moritz, C. H., Quigley, M. A., & Meyerand, M. E. (2000). Mapping functionally related regions of brain with functional connectivity MR imaging. American Journal of Neuroradiology, 21, 1636–1644.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, B., & Pomeau, Y. (1986). Random networks of automata: A simple annealed approximation. Europhysics Letters, 1, 45–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elowitz, M. B., & Leibler, S. (2000). A synthetic oscillatory network of transcriptional regulators. Nature, 403, 335–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erdös, P., & Rényi, A. (1960). On the evolution of random graphs. Proceedings of the Mathematical Institute of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences, 5, 17–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ermentrout, G. B., & Kopell, N. (1984). Frequency plateaus in a chain of weakly coupled oscillators. 1. Siam Journal on Mathematical Analysis, 15, 215–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felleman, D. J., & van Essen, D. C. (1991). Distributed hierarchical processing in the primate cerebral cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 1, 1–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flyvbjerg, H. (1988). An order parameter for networks of automata. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and General, 21, L955–L960.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 50–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342–S353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldbeter, A. (1995). A model for circadian oscillations in the Drosophila period protein (PER). Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 261, 319–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, B. C. (1965). Oscillatory behavior in enzymatic control processes. Advances in Enzyme Regulation, 3, 425–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, S., Levy, A., & Bechtel, W. (2015). Design sans adaptation. European Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 5, 15–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greicius, M. D., Krasnow, B., Reiss, A. L., & Menon, V. (2003). Functional connectivity in the resting brain: A network analysis of the default mode hypothesis. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 100, 253–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greicius, M. D., Supekar, K., Menon, V., & Dougherty, R. F. (2009). Resting-state functional connectivity reflects structural connectivity in the default mode network. Cerebral Cortex, 19, 72–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagmann, P., Cammoun, L., Gigandet, X., Meuli, R., Honey, C. J., Wedeen, V. J., & Sporns, O. (2008). Mapping the structural core of human cerebral cortex. PLoS Biology, 6, e159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, P. E., Hall, J. C., & Rosbash, M. (1990). Feedback of the Drosophila period gene product on circadian cycling of its messenger RNA levels. Nature, 343, 536–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • He, Y., Wang, J., Wang, L., Chen, Z. J., Yan, C., Yang, H., Tang, H., Zhu, C., Gong, Q., Zang, Y., & Evans, A. C. (2009). Uncovering intrinsic modular organization of spontaneous brain activity in humans. PLoS One, 4, e5226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubel, D. H., & Wiesel, T. N. (1962). Receptive fields, binocular interaction and functional architecture in the cat’s visual cortex. Journal of Physiology, 160, 106–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubel, D. H., & Wiesel, T. N. (1968). Receptive fields and functional architecture of monkey striate cortex. Journal of Physiology, 195, 215–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Issad, T., & Malaterre, C. (2015). Are dynamic mechanistic explanations still mechanistic? In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 265–292). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeong, H., Mason, S. P., Barabasi, A. L., & Oltvai, Z. N. (2001). Lethality and centrality in protein networks. Nature, 411, 41–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, N. (2014). Bowtie structures, pathway diagrams, and topological explanation. Erkenntnis, 79, 1135–1155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, N., & Wolkenhauer, O. (2012). Diagrams as locality aids for explanation and model construction in cell biology. Biology and Philosophy, 27, 705–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalir, S., Mangan, S., & Alon, U. (2005). A coherent feed-forward loop with a SUM input function prolongs flagella expression in Escherichia coli. Molecular Systems Biology, 1, 2005.0006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. A. (1969). Metabolic stability and epigenesis in randomly constructed genetic nets. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 22(3), 437–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. A. (1974). The large scale structure and dynamics of gene control circuits: An ensemble approach. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 44(1), 167–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. A. (1993). The origins of order: Self-organization and selection in evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Konopka, R. J., & Benzer, S. (1971). Clock mutants of Drosophila melanogaster. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 89, 2112–2116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kopell, N., & Ermentrout, G. B. (1988). Coupled oscillators and the design of central pattern generators. Mathematical Biosciences, 90, 87–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuramoto, Y. (1984). Chemical oscillations, waves, and turbulence. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli, S., Ramsden, E., Nelson, N., & Ankeny, R. A. (2014). Making organisms model humans: Situated models in alcohol research. Science in Context, 27(3), 485–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A., & Bechtel, W. (2013). Abstraction and the organization of mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 80, 241–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luque, B., & Solé, R. (1997). Phase transitions in random networks: Simple analytic determination of critical points. Physical Review E, 55, 257–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macnab, R. M. (2003). How bacteria assemble flagella. Annual Review of Microbiology, 57, 77–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mangan, S., Zaslaver, A., & Alon, U. (2003). The coherent feedforward loop serves as a sign-sensitive delay element in transcription networks. Journal of Molecular Biology, 334, 197–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mangan, S., Itzkovitz, S., Zaslaver, A., & Alon, U. (2006). The incoherent feed-forward loop accelerates the response-time of the gal system of Escherichia coli. Journal of Molecular Biology, 356, 1073–1081.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mantini, D., Perrucci, M. G., Del Gratta, C., Romani, G. L., & Corbetta, M. (2007). Electrophysiological signatures of resting state networks in the human brain. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104, 13170–13175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meunier, R. (2012). Stages in the development of a model organism as a platform for mechanistic models in developmental biology: Zebrafish, 1970–2000. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 522–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milo, R., Shen-Orr, S., Itzkovitz, S., Kashtan, N., Chklovskii, D., & Alon, U. (2002). Network motifs: Simple building blocks of complex networks. Science, 298, 824–827.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Minami, Y., Ode, K. L., & Ueda, H. R. (2013). Mammalian circadian clock: The roles of transcriptional repression and delay. Handbook of Experimental Pharmacology, 217, 359–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overton, J. A. (2011). Mechanisms, types, and abstractions. Philosophy of Science, 78, 941–954.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rohlf, T., & Bornholdt, S. (2002). Criticality in random threshold networks: Annealed approximation and beyond. Physica A: Statistical Mechanics and its Applications, 310, 245–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenblueth, A., Wiener, N., & Bigelow, J. (1943). Behavior, purpose, and teleology. Philosophy of Science, 10, 18–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shen-Orr, S. S., Milo, R., Mangan, S., & Alon, U. (2002). Network motifs in the transcriptional regulation network of Escherichia coli. Nature Genetics, 31, 64–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shulman, G. L., Corbetta, M., Buckner, R. L., Fiez, J. A., Miezin, F. M., Raichle, M. E., & Petersen, S. E. (1997). Common blood flow changes across visual tasks: I. increases in subcortical structures and cerebellum but not in nonvisual cortex. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 9, 624–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solé, R. V., & Valverde, S. (2006). Are network motifs the spandrels of cellular complexity? Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 21, 419–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O., & Kötter, R. (2004). Motifs in brain networks. PLoS Biology, 2, e369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O., & Zwi, J. D. (2004). The small world of the cerebral cortex. Neuroinformatics, 2, 145–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O., Tononi, G., & Kötter, R. (2005). The human connectome: A structural description of the human brain. PLoS Computational Biology, 1, e42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stricker, J., Cookson, S., Bennett, M. R., Mather, W. H., Tsimring, L. S., & Hasty, J. (2008). A fast, robust and tunable synthetic gene oscillator. Nature, 456, 516–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Théry, F. (2015). Explaining in contemporary molecular biology: Beyond mechanisms. In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 113–133). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyson, J. J., & Novák, B. (2010). Functional motifs in biochemical reaction networks. Annual Review of Physical Chemistry, 61, 219–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ueda, H. R., Hayashi, S., Chen, W., Sano, M., Machida, M., Shigeyoshi, Y., Iino, M., & Hashimoto, S. (2005). System-level identification of transcriptional circuits underlying mammalian circadian clocks. Nature Genetics, 37, 187–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van den Heuvel, M. P., Mandl, R. C. W., Kahn, R. S., & Pol, H. E. H. (2009). Functionally linked resting-state networks reflect the underlying structural connectivity architecture of the human brain. Human Brain Mapping, 30, 3127–3141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, J. J., & Thornton, J. M. (2007). Evolutionary models for formation of metwork motifs and modularity in the Saccharomyces transcription factor network. PLoS Computational Biology, 3, e198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watts, D., & Strogratz, S. (1998). Collective dynamics of small worlds. Nature, 393, 440–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, J. G. (1985). Neuronal connectivity in Caenorhabditis elegans. Trends in Neurosciences, 8, 277–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, J. G., Southgate, E., Thomson, J. N., & Brenner, S. (1986). The structure of the nervous system of the nematode Caenorhabditis elegans. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. B Biological Sciences, 314, 1–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winfree, A. T. (1967). Biological rhythms and the behavior of populations of coupled oscillators. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 16, 15–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2013). II—Mechanistic explanation: Its scope and limits. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 87, 39–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, M. P. (1993). The organization of neural systems in the primate cerebral cortex. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences, 252, 13–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, E. E., & Kay, S. A. (2010). Clocks not winding down: Unravelling circadian networks. Nature Reviews Molecular and Cell Biology, 11, 764–776.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

Initial research on this project began when I was a Fellow at the Institute for Advanced Studies at Hebrew University. I thank the members of the group for productive discussions and especially Arnon Levy for introducing me to the work of Uri Alon and facilitating a meeting with him. Subsequently I have benefited from many further discussions with Arnon and with Sara Green. I presented much of the material here at colloquia at the University of California, Irvine and the University of Cincinnati, at workshop at the University of Wollongong, and to the reunion conference of the research group at the Institute for Advanced Studies. I thank the audiences at these various forums for very helpful comments. I also thank members of the WORGODS research group (Adele Abrahamsen, Daniel Burnston, and Benjamin Sheredos) at the University of California, San Diego for valuable discussion of the diagrammatic representations of circadian clock mechanisms. Thanks as well to Marta Halina and to the editors of this volume, Pierre-Alain Braillard and Christophe Malaterre, for valuable comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William Bechtel .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bechtel, W. (2015). Generalizing Mechanistic Explanations Using Graph-Theoretic Representations. In: Explanation in Biology. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 11. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9822-8_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics