Skip to main content
  • 95 Accesses

Abstract

Auguste Comte, Émile Durkheim, Raymond Aron and Louis Althusser, among others, all claimed Montesquieu to be the first to discover the social.2 Such a claim, despite or because of the diversity of the claimants, is entirely conventional, at least among French authors. By revisiting this convention, I am defending the claim—although I admit to more than one discovery. Moreover, these authors all claim that social analysis arose in opposition to the formerly dominant political (and implicitly, metaphysical) schemas. But this latter claim begs a number of questions, and it is in the response to these questions that my analysis seeks to cut its own path. How is the separation of the social from the political made possible? What is this ‘social’ that by being separated appears for the first time? What kind of ‘object’ is it? What does its emergence mean for the comprehension of—and by implication, action on—collective life? And what are the implications of this separation as it rebounds onto the political? To highlight my difference from the more common responses, I want to begin with a brief examination of Émile Durkheim’s writings on Montesquieu. I choose Durkheim’s writings because they are far more extensive than those of Comte, more emphatic than those of Aron, and in crucial respects similar to those of Althusser.3 Besides, Durkheim is a perennial favourite in classical sociology courses.

When I recollect what the President Montesquieu has written, I am at a loss to tell why I should treat of human affairs …’

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Adam Ferguson, An Essay on the History of Civil Society (London: Transaction Books [1767] 1980), p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Auguste Comte, Physique sociale. Cours de philosophie positive: Leçons 46 à 60 (Paris: Hermann, 1975 [1842]), 85;

    Google Scholar 

  3. Émile Durkheim, Montesquieu and Rousseau: Forerunners of Sociology (Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1960);

    Google Scholar 

  4. Louis Althusser, Montesquieu, la politique et l’histoire (Paris: PUF, 1959)

    Google Scholar 

  5. [Reprinted in English in Politics and History: Montesquieu, Rousseau, Hegel, Marx (London: NLB, 1972)]; Raymond Aron, Les étapes de la pensée sociologique (Paris: Gallimard, 1967). [Main Currents in Sociological Thought, trans. Richard Howard and Helen Weaver (New York: Basic Books, 1965)].

    Google Scholar 

  6. Emile Durkheim, The Division of Labour in Society (1893) trans. George Simpson (New York: The Free Press, 1964).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Another example: L. Thomas, Pangle, Montesquicu’s Philosophy of Liberalism: A Commentary on The Spirit of the Laws (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1973), pp. 44–5.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Admittedly, physiocracy was concerned more with what would become the science of economics. See Elizabeth Fox-Genovese, The Origins of Physiocracy: Economic Revolutions and Social Order in Eighteenth Century France (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1976);

    Google Scholar 

  9. and Ronald L. Meek, The Economics of Physiocracy: Essays and Translations (Fairfield, NJ: Harvard University Press, 1993), among other works.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Though the central concern of the idéologues was with moral phenomena, which they equated with the socio-political order, their method led them to treat ideas as facts, whose operations could then be studied empirically. See Georges Gusdorf, La conscience révolutionnaire: Les idéologues (Paris: Payot, 1978);

    Google Scholar 

  11. Laurent Clauzade, L’Idéologie ou la révolution de l’analyse (Paris: Gallimard, 1998); and Robert Wokler, ‘Ideology and the Origins of Social Science’.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Note that reason is not deemed immanent to the nature of the world, let alone to man’s nature. Montesquieu does not hold to what Leo Strauss would call ‘modern natural law’, a point also made with considerable brio by Jean Goldzink, La solitude de Montesquieu: Le chef-d’oeuvre introuvable du libéralisme (Paris: Fayard, 2011).

    Google Scholar 

  13. De l’Esprit des lois was first published outside France to avoid censorship; it would still be condemned and a copy burned on the steps of the Sorbonne. Subsequent editions would include concessions on minor points; but no concessions could be made regarding the larger hierarchical order, and the place of God in it. See Jonathan Israel, Enlightenment Contested: Philosophy, Modernity, and the Emancipation of Man, 1670–1752 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 824–39.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. Hume, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. Tom Beauchamp (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988 [1777]), p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  15. The claim is made by Patrick Riley, The General Will Before Rousseau (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press 1986);

    Google Scholar 

  16. and Paul-Laurent Assoun, ‘Les sources philosophiques du concept de loi dans l’Esprit des lois: Montesquieu et le malbranchisme’, in Analyses& réflexions sur Montesquieu, De l’esprit des lois: la nature et la loi, ed. Joël Askénazi et al. (Paris: Ellipses, 1987). Thomas Pangle argues that, by claiming the generality of the law, Montesquieu is indicating that his ideas refer to the classical rather than a Christian realm of ideas (Montesquieu’s Philosophy of Liberalism, p. 24). It is typical of Straussians to miss the references to more recent authors. Whether Malebranche believed that God violated general laws to produce ‘miracles’ is a rather vexed question. Clearly Malebranche held that general laws are on occasion violated, but such violations cannot be contrary to God’s nature. As such, Malebranche suggests that miracles may be general laws of a higher nature, surpassing all human understanding.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See David Scott, On Malebranche (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 2002), pp. 13–4.

    Google Scholar 

  18. The conception of representation presented here is not unlike that described by Louis Marin, Portrait of the King (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1988 [1981]), pp. 1–15. The paradigmatic case of this conception is the host that represents the body of Christ in the Catholic mass.

    Google Scholar 

  19. It should be clear that we do not follow Jonathan Israel’s suggestion that, even if Montesquieu is tied to the ‘moderate Enlightenment’, his philosophical roots lie in Spinoza, Bayle and Boulainvilliers . To situate Montesquieu in relation to hierarchical modes of thinking is to remove him from all forms of philosophical monism. Enlightenment Contested (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 268–83.

    Google Scholar 

  20. The ultimate reference in my rather polemical construction of a republican epistemology is, once again, ‘modern natural law’ or ‘natural jurisprudence’, with its claim that the juridical order (and, by implication, the moral and political order) is to be understood as constituted on the basis of human powers alone (whether rooted in human nature, human sociability, passions, interests, conscience or reason). For classical accounts of modern natural law, see Otto Friedrich von Gierke, Natural Law and the Theory of Society 1500–1800, 2 vols., trans. E. Barker (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1934 [1913]);

    Google Scholar 

  21. and Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1950).

    Google Scholar 

  22. For a more contemporary reading of modern natural law, I recommend the writings of Knud Haakonssen, notably, Natural Law and Moral Philosophy: From Grotius to the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  23. As Neil G. Robertson points out, unlike the state of nature in Rousseau, Montesquieu’s state of nature is not self-sufficient, and does not therefore require a catastrophe to initiate the transition to social existence. ‘Rousseau, Montesquieu and the Origins of Inequality’, Animus: The Canadian Journal of Philosophy and Humanities, 12 (2008), http://www2.swgc.mun.ca/animus/Articles/Volume%2012/Robertsonl2. pdf.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Brian C. J. Singer, ‘Intellectuals and Democracy: The Three Figures of Knowledge and Power’, CTHEORY, http://www.ctheory.net/default.asp, Article: A147 (12 January 2004).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2013 Brian C.J. Singer

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Singer, B.C.J. (2013). The Question Concerning Laws. In: Montesquieu and the Discovery of the Social. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137027702_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics