Skip to main content
Log in

Cosmological lore—and some heresies

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Cosmology is based on a number of well-founded assumptions, which include Hubble's law and the cosmological principle. Most cosmologists and astronomers also tacitly accept a number of other assumptions and beliefs which constitute a sort of traditional cosmological lore. Among these are the notions that the universe is finite, that if it is not, then there must be an observational horizon which renders it finite for all practical purposes, that it is valid to employ the special relativistic Doppler formula to interpret large cosmological redshifts, and that the expansion of the universe is slowing down toward its ultimate reversal. It is argued that none of these notions is incontrovertible and that some of them involve serious inconsistencies. An alternative approach is proposed which assumes that the universe is expanding uniformly and that it constitutes a fundamental reference frame for light propagation as implied by the Robertson-Walker metric. This approach leads to a model of the universe which is possibly infinite but without a specific observational horizon, and which satisfies the requirements of relativity. It is shown that the proposed model is theoretically consistent and that recent astronomical evidence supports its assumptions and predictions; it therefore presents a serious challenge to commonly held views about the universe.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. S. W. Hawking and G. F. R. Ellis,The Large Scale Features of Space-time, Cambridge U.P. (1973).

  2. E. A. Milne,Kinematic Relativity, Oxford U. P. (1948).

  3. P. A. M. Dirac,Proc. Roy. Soc. A 338, 446 (1974).

    Google Scholar 

  4. V. Fock,The Theory of Space, Time and Gravitation, Pergamon (1959).

  5. W. Davidson and J. V. Narlikar,Rep. Prog. Phys. 29, 539 (1966).

    Google Scholar 

  6. A. Einstein,Ann. Phys. 17, 891 (1905).

    Google Scholar 

  7. H. Bondi, inCosmology Now, J. Laurie, ed., BBC (1973), p. 14.

  8. M. Rees, inCosmology Now, J. Laurie, ed., BBC (1973), p. 137.

  9. J. C. Pecker, A. P. Roberts, and J.-P. Vigier,Nature 237, 227 (1972).

    Google Scholar 

  10. W. H. McCrea,Proc. Math. Soc. Univ. S'ton 5, 15 (1962).

    Google Scholar 

  11. H. Bondi,Observatory 82, 133 (1962).

    Google Scholar 

  12. P. G. Bergmann,Found. Phys. 1, 17 (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  13. G. Builder,Aust. J. Phys. 11, 279 (1958).

    Google Scholar 

  14. S. J. Prokhovnik,Found. Phys. 3, 351 (1973).

    Google Scholar 

  15. S. J. Prokhovnik,The Logic of Special Relativity, Cambridge U. P. (1967).

  16. G. Builder,Aust. J. Phys. 11, 457 (1958).

    Google Scholar 

  17. E. R. Harrison,Nature 260, 591 (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  18. S. J. Prokhovnik,Proc. Camb. Phil. Soc. 67, 391 (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  19. S. J. Prokhovnik,Nature 225, 359 (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  20. A. Sandage,Astrophys. J. 202, 563 (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  21. J. E. Gunn and B. M. Tinsley,Nature 257, 454 (1975).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Prokhovnik, S.J. Cosmological lore—and some heresies. Found Phys 6, 687–705 (1976). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00708948

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00708948

Keywords

Navigation