Skip to main content
Log in

Eliminating Terms of Confusion: Resolving the Liberal–Republican Dispute

  • Published:
The Journal of Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

John Rawls thinks republicanism is compatible with his political liberalism. Philip Pettit insists that the two conflict in important ways. In this paper, I make sense of this dispute by employing David Chalmers’s method of elimination to reveal the meaning underlying key terms in Rawls’s political liberalism and Pettit’s republicanism. This procedure of disambiguating terms will show how the two theories defend the same institutional arrangement on the same grounds. The procedure thus vindicates Rawls’s view of the two theories being compatible. The reason for this compatibility is that both theories are politicized—that is, they are constructed to attract the compliance of all reasonable members of a modern, pluralistic society.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. However, Pettit (2014: 24) suggests that although Rawls and Ronald Dworkin see freedom as non-interference, they are examples of liberals that lean somewhat towards a republican conception of freedom by holding that legal institution can secure rather than compromise individuals’ freedom. Costa (2009) goes further by arguing that Rawls’s conception of freedom is that of non-domination. Rawls (1999: 176) himself says he tries to avoid any debate concerning the meaning of liberty.

  2. Others have also found important similarities between liberalism and republicanism. In his review of Pettit (1997), Roger Boesche (1998: 863) goes so far as to conclude that Pettit’s ‘whole ideal of freedom as nondomination is simply one variant of liberalism, a conclusion that certainly deflates and diminishes the central argument of the book’. Charles Larmore (2001; 2003) reaches a similar conclusion based on Pettit’s concern with respect for the individual.

  3. A comprehensive doctrine, Rawls (2005: 13) explains, is a set of convictions about how to live, which includes conceptions of the good, how we ought to treat others, and ‘much else that is to inform our conduct, and in the limit to our life as a whole’. A person’s ‘conception of the good’ consists of the ends and purposes the person considers worthy of her or his pursuit over a complete life (Rawls 2005: 104).

  4. Rawls never actually addresses Pettit in his discussion of republicanism. But as I show below, Rawls’s account of republicanism is compatible with Pettit’s, and we can therefore understand this issue as a dispute between Rawls and Pettit.

  5. By focusing on Pettit and Rawls’s theories, I inevitably leave some variants of republicanism and liberalism unexplored. But Pettit and Rawls are leading figures in contemporary republicanism and liberalism, respectively. For a defence of the use of  the method of elimination in political philosophy, see Bosworth (2020).

  6. By identifying the aim of his theory to be minimal domination, Pettit (1997: 97–109; 2012a: 123–125; 2017: 337–339) understands it as consequentialist. Rawls (1999: 19–24), on the other hand, is famously opposed to consequentialism. The result of this paper, however, shows that this difference has no implications regarding what institutions they prescribe. In fact, Pettit (2012b) thinks Rawls is a consequentialist—he indeed thinks all political philosophers are consequentialists.

  7. Republicans may, of course, continue to hold that their terminology is superior to that of political liberalism because it has greater rhetorical power, and consequently offers a more effective way of defending liberal institutions. I ignore this matter because it is not what is at stake in the dispute between Pettit and Rawls, and because disputes strictly over terminology is no concern in political philosophy understood as a discipline focusing on the justification and functioning of social and political institutions.

  8. It is difficult to give an explanatory example of a bedrock concept, since any attempt to do so will be controversial. However, Chalmers (2011: 550) notes that ‘some moral theorists may regard ‘ought’ as bedrock, while others may regard ‘right’ or ‘good’ as bedrock’.

  9. Pettit used to refer to such interference as ‘arbitrary interference’, but he now prefers ‘uncontrolled interference’ for two reasons (Pettit 2012a: 58). First, he wants to avoid confusion with ‘arbitrary’ as it is commonly used to describe interference that does not conform to established rules. Interference conforming to established rules may still be uncontrolled, on Pettit’s account, as rules need not be in the interest of those subject to them. Second, ‘arbitrary’ is often used to refer to something that is morally wrong or objectionable, and Pettit wants to avoid this connotation to a moral standard.

  10. Pettit uses the terms ‘neo-Athenian’, ‘Franco-German’, and ‘Continental’ republicanism when he refers to what Rawls calls ‘civic humanism’. Since this theory sees political participation as a necessary component of freedom and the good life, Pettit sees it as importantly different from the ‘neo-Roman’ or ‘Italian-Atlantic’ republicanism that he favours.

  11. See also Rawls (2005: 291) for a similar but less specific list.

  12. Education is an important way of encouraging such virtue. Rawls (2001: 156) notes that in addition to giving children knowledge about the basic liberties, ‘education should also prepare them to be fully cooperating members of society and enable them to be self-supporting; it should also encourage the political virtues so that they want to honor the fair terms of social cooperation in their relations with the rest of society’.

  13. Rawls is less specific than Pettit is about which particular institutions he sees as necessary, but the institutions Pettit see as key in his theory—the mixed constitution, the rule of law, separation of powers, and a contestatory citizenry—seem no less important for Rawls. As already mentioned above, Pettit (2012a: 11) also acknowledges that these institutions are commonly given important roles also in liberal theories.

  14. They might, for example, agree on ‘justice as fairness’, which is the conception of justice Rawls (1999) defends in his early work. Later, however, he describes as just one possible political conception (Rawls 2005).

  15. In A Theory of Justice, the formulation of this principle reads: ‘Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all’ (Rawls 1999: 266).

  16. Pettit cites the 1971 edition of A Theory of Justice at page 233. For the sake of consistency, I cite the revised 1999 edition. The passage in focus here is identical in the two editions.

  17. Susan Moller Okin (1993: 1010) and Brian Barry (1995) go so far as to argue that a political conception of justice can contain no more than the first principle of justice as fairness.

  18. By thus arguing that satisfying Rawls’s first principle is sufficient for non-domination, I challenge Alan Thomas’s (2017: 375, n. 19) view of the difference principle as exactly what republicans need ‘to make domination structurally impossible’. Andrés de Francisco (2006: 279), similarly, suggests the rational parties in Rawls’s original position would choose the same two principles as in justice as fairness if they were motivated to minimize domination.

References

  • Barry, Brian. 1995. John Rawls and the Search for Stability. Ethics 105(4): 874–915.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 2002. Liberty, ed. Henry Hardy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Boesche, Roger. 1998. Thinking about Freedom. Political Theory 26(6): 855–873.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bosworth, William. 2020. An Interpretation of Political Argument. European Journal of Political Theory 19(3): 293–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, Geoffrey, and Philip Pettit. 2005. The feasibility issue. In The oxford handbook of contemporary philosophy, ed. Frank Jackson and Michael Smith, 258–279. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David J. 2011. Verbal Disputes. Philosophical Review 120(4): 515–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David J. 2015. Why Isn’t There More Progress in Philosophy? Philosophy 90(1): 3–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costa, M. Victoria. 2009. Rawls on Liberty and Domination. Res Publica 15(4): 397–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Francisco, Andrés. 2006. A Republican Interpretation of the Late Rawls. Journal of Political Philosophy 14(3): 270–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, Charles. 2001. A Critique of Philip Pettit’s Republicanism. Philosophical Issues 11(1): 229–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, Charles. 2003. Liberal and Republican Conceptions of Freedom. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 6(1): 96–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, Christian. 2006. Republican Freedom and the Rule of Law. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 5(2): 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lovett, Frank, and Philip Pettit. 2009. Neorepublicanism: A Normative and Institutional Research Program. Annual Review of Political Science 12(1): 11–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okin, Susan Moller. 1993. Review of Rawls, Political Liberalism. American Political Science Review 87(4): 1010–1011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 1997. Republicanism: a theory of freedom and government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 1998. Reworking Sandel’s Republicanism. Journal of Philosophy 95(2): 73–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2001a. A theory of freedom: from the psychology to the politics of agency. Oxford: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2001b. Institutions. In Encyclopedia of ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, 858–863. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2003. Agency-Freedom and Option-Freedom. Journal of Theoretical Politics 15(4): 387–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2005. The domination complaint. In Nomos 46: political exclusion and domination, ed. Melissa Williams and Stephen Macedo, 87–117. New York, NY: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2008a. Republican freedom: three axioms, four theorems. In Republicanism and political theory, ed. Cécile Laborde and John Maynor, 102–130. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2008b. The basic liberties. In The legacy of H.L.A. Hart: legal, political, and moral philosophy, ed. Matthew H. Kramer, Clair Grant, Ben Colburn, and Antony Hatzistavrou, 201–221. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Pettit, Philip. 2011. The Instability of Freedom as Noninterference: The Case of Isaiah Berlin. Ethics 121(4): 693–716.

  • Pettit, Philip. 2012a. On the people’s terms: a republican theory and model of democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2012b. The inescapability of consequentialism. In Luck, value, and commitment: themes from the ethics of Bernard Williams, ed. Ulrike Heuer and Gerald Lang, 41–70. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2013. Two republican traditions. In Republican democracy: liberty, law and politics, ed. Andreas Niederberger and Philipp Schink, 169–204. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2014. Just freedom: a moral compass for a complex world. London: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2017. Political Realism Meets Civic Republicanism. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 20(3): 331–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quong, Jonathan. 2011. Liberalism without perfection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1980. Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory. Journal of Philosophy 77(9): 515–572.

  • Rawls, John. 1999. A theory of justice, revised edition. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 2001. Justice as fairness: a restatement, ed. Erin Kelly. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

  • Rawls, John. 2005. Political liberalism. Expanded ed. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin. 1998. Liberty before liberalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin. 2002. A Third Concept of Liberty. Proceedings of the British Academy 117: 237–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin. 2008. Freedom as the absence of arbitrary power. In Republicanism and political theory, ed. Cécile Laborde and John Maynor, 83–101. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, Alan. 2017. Republic of equals: predistribution and property-owning democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the participants in the Queen’s University philosophy reading group for their insightful questions and comments, and especially Christine Sypnowich for all her help with organizing my visit to Queen’s. I am also grateful to Will Bosworth, Keith Dowding, and Alex Oprea for written comments and discussion.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lars J. K. Moen.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Moen, L.J.K. Eliminating Terms of Confusion: Resolving the Liberal–Republican Dispute. J Ethics 26, 247–271 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-021-09370-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-021-09370-6

Keywords

Navigation