Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Turn to Imagination in Legal Theory: The Re-Enchantment of the World?

  • Published:
Law and Critique Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Various contemporary legal theorists have turned to ‘imagination’ as a keyword in their accounts of law. This turn is fruitfully considered as a potential response to the modern condition diagnosed by Max Weber as ‘disenchantment’. While disenchantment is often seen as a symptom of a post-metaphysical age, it is best understood as the consummation of metaphysics and not its overcoming. Law’s participation in disenchantment is illustrated by way of Holmes’ parable of the dragon in ‘The Path of the Law’, which illustrates the rationalization and demystification of law. Four ideal–typical turns to ‘imagination’ are identified: the theoretical (turning to imagination as synthesis), the progressive (imagination as empathy), the transformative (imagination as invention) and the nostalgic (imagination as attunement). Most of these turns to imagination remain complicit with disenchantment. ‘Imagination’ often appears only to be harnessed in the service of more conventional keywords of legal thought: theoreticians turn to imagination as synthesis to serve as a form of super-reason; progressives turn to imagination as empathy to make law a more effective instrument; transformatives turn to imagination as invention to serve as a form of super-will. By turning to imagination as attunement, nostalgics come closest to accepting a world that is not masterable, i.e. they come closest to accepting an enchantment that is a gift and not the product of our imaginations. Indeed, modern imaginations are themselves symptoms of disenchantment. If Weber’s diagnostic calls for a human response, it cannot be one of overcoming disenchantment by imaginative re-enchantment: it belongs integrally to enchantment to exceed any and all human capacities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Nihilism is the historical happening where ‘the highest values devaluate themselves’. Nietzsche (1968, p. 9). See also Heidegger (1977b, p. 53). For an account focusing closely on law, see Nonet (1990).

  2. That such a turn is not always aware of itself as a response makes it even more interesting to examine.

  3. One recent example of this turn is Taylor (2004) who focuses on ‘modern social imaginaries’. An anonymous reviewer helpfully pointed out that much recent theory may prefer to use ‘imaginary’ as opposed to ‘imagination’. My focus on ‘imagination’ as a human faculty or capacity raises the question of whether and how human beings can shape their social imaginary. Taylor’s use of ‘imaginary’ and my consideration of ‘imagination’ both operate at a higher level of generality and are much less technical than, e.g., that of Castoriadis (1987).

  4. Weber’s account of disenchantment also points to the impoverishment or shrinking of public life and hence to the possibility of community in our times. What is highest can no longer be shared publically, politically.

  5. I turn to Heidegger and the principle of reason, of ground, in my reading of Fitzpatrick (2001) in Antaki (2003). See also Berkowitz (2010) on Leibniz and codification.

  6. But see Stolzenberg (1999) who distinguishes Bentham’s position on fictions from his position on legal fictions.

  7. These references to Hobbes emphasize his role in a broader story of disenchantment but do not do justice to the complexity and depth of his work. Leviathan is full of wonderful examples of the use of, for example, simile to attack the use of simile as untruthful, politically pernicious and the like. Referring to the imagination, Todd Butler notes, Hobbes appears to ‘rely upon the very faculty he suspects and seeks to restrain’ (2008, p. 142). Whelan also notes how ‘Hobbes himself is paradoxically forced to resort to the eloquence which he otherwise condemns’ (1981, p. 59). As an anonymous reviewer helpfully pointed out, imagination is central to Hobbes’ system and ‘according to many interpreters, even his definition of reason as calculation simply means just a more disciplined form of imagination’. In this vein, Kahn’s careful study shows how Hobbes’ production of an ‘at least in theory—calculable and dependable’ subject involved a re-working, and not simply a denial, of imagination, of mimetic desire (2004, p. 151). Modern rationality or rationalism, then, is not the product of a subtraction of imagination from the human psyche but of its existential modification: it is the product of a critique of one ‘genre’ or ‘plot’ in light of another. The modern separation of the poetic and the propositional paradoxically involves, to borrow Kahn’s choice of words, ‘a radically new poetics’ (1). See also Martel (2007) for an extremely insightful—and radical—reading of Leviathan that emphasizes its ‘metaphors, figures, and other rhetorical devices’ (13).

  8. Imagination (eikasia) makes a famous appearance in Plato’s Republic, particularly in Socrates’ discussion of the image of the divided line in Book VI, 509d–511e. Imagination there appears as an affection in the soul tied to opinion rather than to knowledge proper. More generally, imagination appears as a mimetic faculty tied to copies—even copies of copies—rather than originals. However, just as it is reductive to read Hobbes as a straightforward attack on the imagination, so too is it reductive to read Plato in that manner. For example, Euben (1990) reads Plato’s Republic as a tragedy in the poetic tradition.

  9. But one entirely dependent on the rise of the law report and the depositing of moments of practical wisdom on paper in propositional form.

  10. Note that social justice itself is most likely a secularized version of Christian charity.

  11. Nussbaum notes this possibility. See also Massaro (1989, p. 2113): ‘When pared to its roots, the “empathy” theme … seems not to be a call for more empathy, but for a different ordering of our empathic responses. It represents a hope that certain specific, different and previously disenfranchised voices … will be heard.’

  12. The phrase ‘social imaginary’ is used by Castoriadis who is the subject of a chapter in Thompson’s book.

  13. Recall the roots of modernity and Neuzeit.

  14. At 81, he writes: ‘…it cannot be doubted that the great ages in the history of art were those in which people without an aesthetic consciousness and without our concept of “art” surrounded themselves with creations whose function in religious or secular life could be understood by everyone and which gave no one solely aesthetic pleasure’.

References

  • Abrams, M.H. 1953. The mirror and the lamp: Romantic theory and the critical tradition. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrew, Edward G. 1995. The genealogy of values: The aesthetic economy of Nietzsche and Proust. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antaki, Mark. 2003. Leading modernity (to) a-ground. Australian Feminist Law Journal 19: 115–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antaki, Mark. 2009. The turn to ‘values’ in Canadian constitutional law. In The limitation of charter rights: Critical essays on R. v. Oakes = La limitation des droits de la Charte: essais critiques sur l’arrêt R. c. Oakes, ed. Luc Tremblay, and Grégoire Webber, 155–181. Montreal: Thémis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The human condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1978. The life of the mind. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Auden, W.H. 1958. Law like love. In Selected poetry of W.H. Auden, 62–64. New York: Modern Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bender, John. 1987. Imagining the penitentiary: Fiction and the architecture of mind in eighteenth-century England. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkowitz, Roger. 2010. The gift of science: Leibniz and the modern legal tradition. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Todd. 2008. Imagination and politics in seventeenth-century England. Aldershot, England: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castoriadis, Cornelius. 1987. The imaginary institution of society. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, William. 1993. Political theory and modernity. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Constable, Marianne. 1994. Genealogy and jurisprudence: Nietzsche, nihilism, and the social scientification of law. Law & Social Inquiry 19: 551–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Constable, Marianne. 1995. A new conception of law? Law & Society Review 29: 593–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, Simon. 2004. Very little…almost nothing: Death, philosophy, literature, 2nd ed. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R.M. 1985. A matter of principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R.M. 1986. Law’s empire. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Euben, Peter J. 1990. The tragedy of political theory: The road not taken. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiss, O.M. 1986. The death of law? Cornell Law Review 71: 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, Peter. 1992. The mythology of modern law. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, Peter. 2001. Modernism and the grounds of law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L.L. 1969. The morality of law, rev. ed. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1995. Truth and method, 2nd rev. ed. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Georgiades, Thrasybulos. 1973. Greek music, verse and dance. New York: Da Capo Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R.W. 1984. Critical legal histories. Stanford Law Review 36: 57–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R.W. 1990. New developments in legal theory. In The politics of law: A progressive critique, ed. D. Kairys. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorman, David. 1997. Review of poetic justice: The literary imagination and public life. Philosophy and Literature 21: 196–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. 1994. Postmetaphysical thinking. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halttunen, Karen. 1995. Humanitiarism and the pornography of pain in Anglo-American culture. American Historical Review 100: 303–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1973. Bentham and the demystification of the law. Modern Law Review 36: 2–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1977a. The question concerning technology. In The question concerning technology, and other essays, 3–35. New York: Harper & Row.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1977b. The word of Nietzsche: ‘God is dead’. In The question concerning technology, and other essays, 53–112. New York: Harper & Row.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1977c. The origin of the work of art. In Basic writings, ed. David F. Krell, 139–212. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1991. The principle of reason. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1994. Basic concepts of philosophy: Selected ‘problems’ of ‘logic’. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1994. In Leviathan, ed. Edwin Curley. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett.

  • Holmes, O.W. 1897. The path of the law. Harvard Law Review 10: 457–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, Lynn. 2007. Inventing human rights: A history. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, A.C. 1984. From cultural construction to historical deconstruction. (Book review of James Boyd White, When words lose their meaning: Constitutions and reconstitutions of language, character, and community). Yale Law Journal 94: 209–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jameson, F. 1972. The prison-house of language: A critical account of structuralism and Russian formalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, Victoria. 2004. Wayward contracts: The crisis of political obligation in England, 1640–1674. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearney, R. 1988. The wake of imagination: Toward a postmodern culture. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Koselleck, R. 2002. The practice of conceptual history: Timing history, spacing concepts. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kronman, A.T. 1993. The lost lawyer: Failing ideals of the legal profession. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martel, James R. 2007. Subverting the Leviathan: Reading Thomas Hobbes as a radical democrat. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massaro, T.M. 1989. Legal storytelling: Empathy, legal storytelling, and the rule of law: New words, Old wounds? Michigan Law Review 87: 2099–2127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl. 1978. The German ideology: Part I. In The Marx–Engels reader, 2nd ed, ed. Robert C. Tucker, 146–200. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, Linda Ross. 2010. The justice of mercy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F.W. 1968. The will to power. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nonet, Philippe. 1990. What is positive law? Yale Law Journal 100: 667–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 1986. The fragility of goodness: Luck and ethics in Greek tragedy and philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 1990. ‘Finely aware and richly responsible’: Literature and the moral imagination. In Love’s knowledge: Essays on philosophy and literature, 148–167. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 1995. Poetic justice. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orwell, George. 1982. Politics and the English language. In Orwell’s Nineteen Eighty-Four: Text, sources, criticisms, 2nd ed, ed. Irving Howe, 248–258. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos, Boaventura de Sousa 1995. Three metaphors for a new conception of law. Law & Society Review 29: 569–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slaughter, Joseph R. 2007. Human rights, Inc.: The world novel, narrative form, and international law. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sossin, L.M. 1997. The politics of imagination. University of Toronto Law Review 47: 523–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 2004. Modern social imaginaries. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stolzenberg, Nomi Maya. 1999. Bentham’s theory of fictions—a ‘curious double language’. Cardozo Studies in Law and Literature 11: 223–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, J.B. 1984. Studies in the theory of ideology. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1983. The critical legal studies movement. Harvard Law Review 96: 561–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1984. Passion: An essay on personality. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1987a. False necessity: Anti-necessitarian social theory in the service of radical democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1987b. Social theory: Its situation, its task. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1996. What should legal analysis become? London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, Ian. 2002. The echo of a sentimental jurisprudence. Law and Critique 13: 107–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1946. Science as a vocation. In From Max Weber: Essays in sociology, ed. H. Gerth, and C.W. Mills, 129–156. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1958. The Protestant ethic and the spirit of capitalism. New York: Scribner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whelan, Frederick G. 1981. Language and its abuses in Hobbes’ political philosophy. American Political Science Review. 75: 59–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, James Boyd. 1984. The judicial opinion and the poem: Ways of reading, ways of life. Michigan Law Review 82: 1669–1700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, James Boyd. 1985. The legal imagination, abridged ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, James Boyd. 1986. Introduction: Is cultural criticism possible? Michigan Law Review 84: 1373–1388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, James Boyd. 1987a. Law as rhetoric, rhetoric as law: The arts of cultural and communal life. University of Chicago Law Review 52: 684–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, James Boyd. 1987b. Thinking about our language. Yale Law Journal 96: 1960–1984.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, James Boyd. 1990. Justice as translation: An essay in cultural and legal criticism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, James Boyd. 1994. Acts of hope: Creating authority in literature, law, and politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Raymond. 1985. Keywords: A vocabulary of culture and society, rev. ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, R.G. 1996. Whose phronesis? Which phronimoi?: A response to Dean Kronman on law school education. Cumberland Law Review 26: 817–842.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yelle, Robert A. 2005. Bentham’s fictions: Canon and idolatry in the genealogy of law. Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities 17: 151–179.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the many people who commented on previous versions of this essay or who gave me their comments when I presented it orally at several workshops and conferences. Part of the reflection on this essay was done during a fellowship at the Stellenbosch Institute of Advanced Study, for which I am grateful.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Antaki.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Antaki, M. The Turn to Imagination in Legal Theory: The Re-Enchantment of the World?. Law Critique 23, 1–20 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10978-011-9095-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10978-011-9095-0

Keywords

Navigation