Skip to main content
Log in

Substance concepts and personal identity

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to one argument for Animalism about personal identity, animal, but not person, is a Wigginsian substance concept—a concept that tells us what we are essentially. Person supposedly fails to be a substance concept because it is a functional concept that answers the question “what do we do?” without telling us what we are. Since person is not a substance concept, it cannot provide the criteria for our coming into or going out of existence; animal, on the other hand, can provide such criteria. This argument has been defended by Eric Olson, among others. I argue that this line of reasoning fails to show Animalism to be superior to the Psychological Approach, for the following two reasons: (1) human animal, animal, and organism are all functional concepts, and (2) the distinction between what something is and what it does is illegitimate on the reading that the argument needs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Snowdon (1990), Olson (1997), and DeGrazia (2005) are prominent defenders of Animalism.

  2. Wiggins (1967, 1980, 2001).

  3. Olson (1997).

  4. Carter (1982) also engages this issue, and also argues that person is not a substance concept, though he does not defend animalism.

  5. Lewis (1976); Parfit (1984); Shoemaker (1984), and Noonan (1989) each defend different types of psychological continuity theories of personal identity.

  6. See Nozick (1981).

  7. See Nagel (1986).

  8. Although, as is well-known, Parfit has argued that identity is not “what matters” in survival. Still, even Parfit agrees that identity usually contingently coincides with what matters.

  9. Shoemaker’s (1962) “Brown and Brownson” case is the first brain transfer thought experiment. It is a contemporary version of Locke’s (1995/1693) much earlier soul transfer thought experiment. The overwhelming intuitive response to both thought experiments is that a person follows his or her psychology (whether that psychology is grounded in a soul, brain, or something else), even if that psychology leaves one’s own body. Olson (1997) believes that the brain transfer case is neutral between the Psychological Approach and Animalism, and thus proposes a cerebrum transfer case. If we believe that we go where our cerebrum goes, that allegedly supports the Psychological Approach, although Olson argues that it only supports a Psychological Approach to what matters—not identity.

  10. My interpretation of Olson here is based on what he says in Chap. 2 and p. 121 of The Human Animal.

  11. This use of ‘person’ appears to be a descendent of the Lockean conception of ‘person’ as a forensic term, perhaps with some modifications Locke (1995/1693).

  12. Olson (1997, p. 130).

  13. DeGrazia (2005).

  14. DeGrazia (2005, pp. 30–31). The PA, he says, could just accept the de dicto thesis that psychological continuity is required in order for one to continue to exist qua person. In his (1997), Olson seems to think that all versions of the PA are committed to person essentialism, but he qualifies this to “nearly all” in his (1999).

  15. If we are allowing for the possibility of adopting the de dicto thesis, then what follows is that all versions of versions of PA that rely on person essentialism are false.

  16. Aristotle, Categories, Metaphysics, Book Z; Wiggins (1967, 1980, 2001).

  17. Wiggins (2001, p. 21).

  18. Olson (1997, p. 32.

  19. The view that identity is dependent on a sortal (but not relative to a sortal) comes from Wiggins (1967, 1980, 2001). Although it is not uncontroversial, it is a widely accepted view of identity.

  20. Olson (1997, pp. 32–36).

  21. Olson (1997, p. 35), emphasis added.

  22. Olson (1997, pp. 34–35), emphasis of ‘dispositional’, ‘functional’, and ‘intrinsic structures’ added.

  23. According to Snowdon (1990) “Surely if we ask to what entities the functional predicate (person), as elucidated by Locke, does apply, the answer we all want to give is—a certain kind of animal, namely human beings” (p. 90). DeGrazia (2005) claims that “Rather than regarding personhood as a basic kind, we should regard it as comprising a set of capacities that things of different basic kinds might achieve. On this view, personhood represents merely a phase of our existence” (p. 49).

  24. DeGrazia (2005, p. 49). He gives the same sort of argument against McMahan’s (2002) “mind essentialism” on p. 71.

  25. Olson (1997): 121.

  26. ibid.

  27. Olson (1997, p. 36).

  28. Indeed, DeGrazia is deliberately noncommittal regarding the precise boundaries of our kind; he insists only that it is biological (2005, pp. 48–49. However, since organism, animal, and human organism are the most plausible of these candidate biological kinds, and since it would be tedious to survey all the other candidates, I shall confine my discussion to these three kinds.

  29. Sober (2000, p. 152).

  30. Rob Wilson (2005) also defines ‘organism’ largely in terms of functional features. He contends that ‘organism’ is best defined by a homeostatic property cluster, in which many of the important properties are functional.

  31. Olson (1997, p. 130), emphasis added.

  32. Hershenov (2005, pp. 49–50), emphasis in original.

  33. See, for instance, Campbell, et al. (1997), and Wallace (1997).

  34. Olson (1997, 2007) affirms that literally, there is no such thing as a dead organism or dead animal.

  35. One might wonder whether this capacity (and perhaps some of the others definitive of animals, organisms, and species) is grounded in an intrinsic, structural feature, such as DNA. (Thanks to Alan Sidelle for suggesting this to me.) That certainly is a live possibility, but this sort of empirical consideration is just as applicable to person. That is to say, if something like Nagel’s (1986) “same brain” view is right, then the property of personhood is indeed grounded in an intrinsic, structural property, namely, the structure of the human brain. So, while I certainly do not mean to presuppose that there is no structure underlying the capacity to reproduce fertile offspring with other individuals, I also think that one should not presuppose that there is no structure underlying the capacity for personhood. So I think that animalism and the Psychological View are on approximately equal footing in this matter.

  36. See Sober (2000), Chap. 6.

  37. Hirsch (1982).

  38. Although some would disagree: see Van Inwagen (1990) and Merricks (2001).

  39. See Van Inwagen (1990) and Merricks (2001).

  40. For example, see Hawking (1988).

  41. Greene (1999, p. 11).

References

  • Aristotle, Categories.

  • Aristotle, Metaphysics.

  • Campbell, N., Mitchell, L., & Reece, J. (1997). Biology: Concepts and connections (2nd ed.). New York: Benjamin/Cummins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, W. R. (1982). Do zygotes become people? Mind, 361, 77–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2005). Human identity and bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, B. (1999). The elegant universe. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawking, S. (1988). A brief history of time. New York: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hershenov, D. (2005). Do dead bodies pose a problem for biological approaches to personal identity? Mind, 114(453), 31–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, E. (1982). The concept of identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1976). Survival and identity. In A. Rorty (Ed.), The identities of persons. Berkeley: The University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1995/1693). An essay concerning human understanding. New York: Prometheus Books.

  • McMahan, J. (2002). The ethics of killing: Problems at the margins of life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2001). Objects and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: A study in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1986). The view from nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noonan, H. (1989). Personal identity. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, Mass: Belnap/Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. (1997). The human animal. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. (1999). Reply to Lynne Rudder Baker. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(1), 161–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. (2007). What are we? A study in personal ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1962). Self-knowledge and self-identity. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1984). Personal identity: A materialist’s account. In S. Shoemaker & R. Swinburne (Eds.), Personal identity (pp. 67–132). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon, P. F. (1990). Persons, animals, and ourselves. In C. Gill (Ed.), The person and the human mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2000). Philosophy of biology (2nd ed.). Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1990). Material beings. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. A. (1997). Biology: The world of life (7th ed.). New York: Benjamin/Cummins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (1967). Identity and spatiotemporal continuity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (1980). Sameness and substance. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (2001). Sameness and substance renewed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. (2005). Genes and the agents of life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For valuable feedback on this article, I would like to thank Mark Anderson, Holly Kantin, Carolina Sartorio, Eric Stencil, and especially Alan Sidelle.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Nichols.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nichols, P. Substance concepts and personal identity. Philos Stud 150, 255–270 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9412-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9412-8

Keywords

Navigation