Skip to main content

Social Policy and the Scope of Political Theory

  • Chapter
Political Theory and Social Policy

Part of the book series: Studies in Social Policy

  • 21 Accesses

Abstract

There are two striking features of the politics of liberal democracies. The first is that, with the qualified exceptions of Japan and the USA, they are all developed welfare states, within each of which there is a widespread consensus about there being a social responsibility for such contingencies as unemployment, old age, sickness, education, housing and social welfare. The second feature is that, despite this consensus, there exists within these countries significant controversy about the exact scope of social responsibility, the form it should take and its consequences for social, economic and political life more generally. This mixture of controversy and consensus presents a problem. How can we reconcile this agreement on basics with so much disagreement about specifics?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. W. Beckerman (ed.), The Labour Government’s Economic Record, 1964–1970 (London: Duckworth, 1972);

    Google Scholar 

  2. Graham Hallett, The Social Economy of West Germany (London: Macmillan, 1973);

    Book  Google Scholar 

  3. J. Leruez, Economic Planning and Politics in Britain (London: Martin Robertson, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  4. For the latest state of the art in these matters see the papers by Geoffrey Stephenson, Michael O’Higgins and Chris Pond in Cedric Sandford, Chris Pond and Robert Walker, Taxation and Social Policy (London: Heinemann, 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  5. The results reported there are in some respects depressingly similar to those in T. Barna, Redistribution of Incomes Through Public Finance in 1937 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1945).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Compare Edgar K. Browning, Redistribution and the Welfare System (Washington: American Enterprise Institute, 1975)

    Google Scholar 

  7. and Peter Townsend, Poverty in the United Kingdom (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1980) pp. 925–6.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Department of Health and Social Security, Prevention and Health: Everybody’s Business (London: HMSO, 1976);

    Google Scholar 

  9. Marc Lalonde, A New Perspective on the Health of Canadians (Ottawa: Information Canada, 1975). In this connection it is worth noting David Reisman’s acute criticism of Titmuss, to the effect that, because Titmuss saw social policy as compensating for the diswelfares of an industrialised economy, he ignored the possibility of regulating industry to prevent those diswelfares arising.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See D. Reisman, Richard Titmuss: Welfare and Society (London: Heinemann, 1977) p. 102.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Compare Robert Pinker, The Idea of Welfare (London: Heinemann, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  12. David Easton, The Political System (New York: Knopf, 1953) pp. 129–34.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development, Public Expenditure Trends (Paris: OECD, 1978) p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Compare Harold L. Wilensky and Charles N. Lebeaux, Industrial Society and Social Welfare (New York: Free Press, 1965).

    Google Scholar 

  15. The best defence of functional explanation as involving more than a heuristic device is to be found in G. A. Cohen, Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defence (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978) chs 9 and 10. Cohen’s claim (pp. 261–2) is that a eufunctional effect can be cited as the explanation of its cause because it allows us to infer that society has some disposition giving rise to the effect. But this seems to ascribe no more than heuristic status to functional modes of discourse. Either the inference is validated, in which case the disposition is the true explanation of the effect, or it is invalidated, in which case it is clear that the eufunctional effect cannot be the explanation. Moreover, is it not a priori implausible to hold that functional discourse can be transferred from the explanation of the behaviour of numerous, relatively shortlived biological populations to the limited number of relatively long-lived societies there have been in the world?

    Google Scholar 

  16. For a good introduction to problems of functional explanation, see the following: Dorothy N. Emmet, Function, Purpose and Powers (London: Macmillan, 1958) chs 3 and 4;

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ernest Nagel, The Structure of Science (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1961) pp. 520–35;

    Google Scholar 

  18. Alan Ryan, The Philosophy of the Social Sciences (London: Macmillan, 1970) ch. 8.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  19. Compare, Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development, Public Expenditure on Income Maintenance Programmes (Paris: OECD, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  20. For good examples in this mode see, Peter Flora and Arnold J. Heidenheimer, The Development of Welfare States in Europe and America (New Brunswick and London: Transaction Books, 1981)

    Google Scholar 

  21. and Gaston V. Rimlinger, Welfare Policy and Industrialisation in Europe, America and Russia (Chichester: Wiley, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  22. See, for example, Ted Honderich, Punishment: The Supposed Justifications (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Compare Edmund Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France (1970), ed. Conor Cruise O’Brien (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1968), p. 152: ‘very plausible schemes, with very pleasing commencements, have often shameful and lamentable conclusions … it is with infinite caution that any man ought to venture upon pulling down an edifice which has answered in any tolerable degree for ages the common purposes of society, or on building it up again, without having models and patterns of approved utility before his eyes’.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Compare Michael Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics (London: Methuen, 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  25. For an introduction to cost-benefit analysis, see Robert Sugden and Alan Williams, The Principles of Practical Cost-Benefit Analysis (Oxford University Press, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation in J. H. Burns and H. L. A. Hart, The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham (London: Athlone Press, 1970) ch. 1;

    Google Scholar 

  27. John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism in H. B. Acton (ed.), Utilitarianism, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government (London: Dent, 1972) ch. 4;

    Google Scholar 

  28. Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics 6th edn (London: Macmillan, 1901) book IV;

    Google Scholar 

  29. J. C. C. Smart, ‘An Outline of a Utilitarian System of Ethics’ in J. C. C. Smart and B. A. O. Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973);

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  30. J. C. Harsanyi, ‘Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility’, Journal of Political Economy, LXIII 4 (1955) pp. 309–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. As well as the literature cited in the above note, see also: D. H. Hodgson, Consequences of Utilitarianism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1967);

    Google Scholar 

  32. David Lyons, Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965);

    Book  Google Scholar 

  33. J. L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  34. The following articles are also relevant and are reprinted in Phillippa Foot (ed.). Theories of Ethics (Oxford University Press, 1967);

    Google Scholar 

  35. J. O. Urmson, ‘The Interpretation of the Moral Philosophy of J. S. Mill’, Philosophical Quarterly, III (1953) pp. 33–9;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. J. D. Mabbott, ‘Interpretations of Mill’s “Utilitarianism”’, Philosophical Review, LXIV (1955) pp. 3–32;

    Google Scholar 

  37. J. C. C. Smart, ‘Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism’, Philosophical Quarterly, VI (1956) pp. 344–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. For historical accounts of what follows, see: Walter Lord, The Past That Would Not Die (London: Hamish Hamilton, 1966);

    Google Scholar 

  39. Arthur M. Schlesinger Jr, A Thousand Days (London: Andre Deutsch, 1965) ch. 35,

    Google Scholar 

  40. Robert Kennedy and His Times (London: Andre Deutsch, 1978) pp.317–27.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Schlesinger, Robert Kennedy, p. 320.

    Google Scholar 

  42. As the Governor himself said, ‘Must it be over one little boy’, quoted in Schlesinger, Robert Kennedy, p. 319.

    Google Scholar 

  43. One way of putting this point is to say that, not only does utilitarianism respond to preferences in an anonymous fashion, it also fails to give special weight to the preferences of the worst-off under alternative social arrangements. For the formal results underlying the informal presentation in the text, see R. Deschamps and L. Gevers, ‘Leximin and Utilitarian Rules: A Joint Characterization’, Journal of Economic Theory, XVII 2 (1978) pp. 143–63,

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. and E. Maskin, ‘A Theorem on Utilitarianism’. Review of Economic Studies, XLV 1 (1978) pp. 93–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Contrast this with Meredith’s own understanding of the events: ‘The question always arises — was it worth the cost? … I believe that I echo the feeling of most Americans when I say that “no price is too high to pay for freedom of person, equality of opportunity, and human dignity”.’ (Schlesinger, Robert Kennedy, p. 325).

    Google Scholar 

  46. Compare T. M. Scanlon, ‘Preferences and Urgency’, Journal of Philosophy, LXXII (1975) pp. 655–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. H. L. A. Hart, ‘Are There Any Natural Rights?’, Philosophical Review, LXIV (1955) pp. 175–91,

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. reprinted in A. Quinton (ed.), Political Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 1967) pp. 53–66.

    Google Scholar 

  49. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972).

    Google Scholar 

  50. For other uses, see in particular: G. R. Grice. The Grounds of Moral Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 1967);

    Google Scholar 

  51. G. Harman, The Nature of Morality (Oxford University Press, 1977); J. C. Harsanyi, ‘Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility’.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Brian Barry, Political Argument (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1965) pp. 3–8, 35–8;

    Google Scholar 

  53. Brian Barry, The Liberal Theory of Justice (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973) p. 6;

    Google Scholar 

  54. Isaiah Berlin, Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford University Press, 1969);

    Google Scholar 

  55. David Miller, Social Justice (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  56. See also W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930).

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1977) ch.6.

    Google Scholar 

  58. H. B. Berrington, How Nations Are Governed (London: Pitman, 1964);

    Google Scholar 

  59. Robert A. Dahl, After The Revolution? (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970);

    Google Scholar 

  60. Isaiah Berlin, Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford University Press, 1969) esp. pp. 167–72.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Plato, The Republic, trans. F. M. Cornford (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1941).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 1983 Albert Weale

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Weale, A. (1983). Social Policy and the Scope of Political Theory. In: Political Theory and Social Policy. Studies in Social Policy. Palgrave, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-17144-6_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics