Skip to main content

Hegel, the State and International Relations

  • Chapter
Classical Theories of International Relations

Part of the book series: St Antony’s Series ((STANTS))

Abstract

The English liberal, L.T. Hobhouse, had no doubt that he was witnessing the most ‘visible and tangible outcome of a false and wicked doctrine’ as he sat annotating Hegel’s writings on freedom in his Highgate garden during a German air-raid in 1917.1 Hobhouse’s critical remarks prefigured the ‘Hegel myth’ in which Hegel was portrayed as a champion of state power and military force.2 Later, Hegel, along with Nietzsche, was thought to have prepared the intellectual groundwork for the rise of Fascism, an interpretation which was stated unequivocally by Sir Karl Popper in The Open Society and its Enemies but debunked in the late 1960s and 1970s.3 The impression which may prevail at present is that Hegel’s writings expressed strident realism rather than proto-Fascism.4

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. L.T. Hobhouse, The Metaphysical Theory of the State: A Criticism (London, 1951), pp. 5–6.

    Google Scholar 

  2. W. Kaufmann (ed.), Hegel’s Political Philosophy (New York, 1970), ch. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  3. J. Morrow, ‘British Idealism, “German Philosophy” and the First World War’, Australian Journal of Politics and History, 28, 1982, pp. 380–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Sir Karl Popper, The Open Society and its Enemies (London, 1945), vol. 2, ch. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  5. F. Northedge, ‘Peace, War and Philosophy’, Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, vol. 6, pp. 63–7 (New York, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  6. F. Meinecke, Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison d’Etat and its Place in Modern History (London, 1962), p. 357.

    Google Scholar 

  7. C. Friedrich, Constitutional Reason of State: The Survival of the Constitutional Order (Providence, Rhode Island, 1957), pp. 92 and 97.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Z. Pelczynski (ed.), Hegel’s Political Philosophy: Problems and Perspectives (Cambridge, 1971), p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  9. S. Avineri, Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge, 1972), p. 207.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. J.E. Toews, Hegelianism: The Path towards Dialectical Humanism, 1805–1841 (Cambridge, 1980), p. 33.

    Google Scholar 

  11. M.L. Shanley and C. Pateman (eds), Feminist Interpretations and Political Theory (Pennsylvania, 1991), p. 134.

    Google Scholar 

  12. M. Oakeshott, On Human Conduct (Oxford, 1975), pp. 262–3. See also Friedrich, op. cit., pp. 92–3.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, ed. J. O’Malley (Cambridge, 1970). On the question of reconciliation with social contradictions

    Google Scholar 

  14. G. Lukács, The Young Hegel: Studies in the Relationship Between Dialectics and Economics (London, 1975), pp. 70 and 146. For an analysis of the differing views of Hegel and Marx on the subject of reconciliation with society,

    Google Scholar 

  15. M.O. Hardiman, ‘The Project of Reconciliation: Hegel’s Social Philosophy’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 21, 2, Spring 1992, pp. 165–95.

    Google Scholar 

  16. R. Plant, ‘Economic and Social Integration in Hegel’s Political Philosophy’, in D.P. Verene (ed.), Hegel’s Social and Political Thought: The Philosophy of Objective Spirit (New Jersey, 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  17. M. Wight, International Theory: The Three Traditions (Leicester, 1991), pp. 53–4.

    Google Scholar 

  18. S. Hoffmann, The State of War: Essays in the Theory and Practice of International Politics (London, 1965), pp. 65–6.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Rousseau, The Social Contract and Discourses (trans. with an introduction by G.D.H. Cole) (London, 1968), p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  20. J. Thompson, Justice and World Order: A Philosophical Inquiry (London, 1992), ch. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  21. R. Plant, Hegel (London, 1973)

    Google Scholar 

  22. C. Taylor, Hegel (Cambridge, 1975).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  23. Z. Pelczynski (ed.), Hegel’s Political Writings (Oxford, 1964), p. 210.

    Google Scholar 

  24. R.J. Vincent, ‘Grotius, Human Rights and Intervention’, in H. Bull, B. Kingsbury and A. Roberts (eds), Hugo Grotius and International Relations (Oxford, 1990), p. 243 (author’s italics).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Hegel, The Philosophy of History, trans. J. Sibree, (New York, 1956), p. 308.

    Google Scholar 

  26. T. O’Hagan, ‘On Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Moral and Political Philosophy’, in S. Priest (ed.), Hegel’s Critique of Kant (Oxford, 1987), p. 157

    Google Scholar 

  27. J. Plamenatz, Man and Society (London, 1963), vol. 2, pp. 266–7.

    Google Scholar 

  28. S. Smith, Hegel’s Critique of Liberalism: Rights in Context (Chicago, 1989), pp. 164 and 169. Martin Wight called this revolutionism which is based on the value of ‘doctrinal uniformity’, International Theory: The Three Traditions op. cit., pp. 41–2.

    Google Scholar 

  29. W.H. Walsh, Hegelian Ethics (London, 1969), p. 22.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  30. M. Riedel, Between Tradition and Revolution: The Hegelian Transformation of Political Philosophy (Cambridge, 1984), pp. 49–50, refers to the ‘universal mind’ which exists alongside the international state of nature. Hedley Bull’s distinction between an international political culture and a diplomatic culture makes a similar point, The Anarchical Society (London, 1977), p. 317.

    Google Scholar 

  31. G.A. Kelly, Hegel’s Retreat from Eleusis: Studies in Political Thought (Princeton, 1978), pp. 19–20 emphasises this point about the state’s location in the wider sphere of civilisation. The 1954 Hague Convention for the Protection of Cultural Property in the Event of Armed Conflict shows how this wider sphere of civilisation can give rise to international obligations.

    Google Scholar 

  32. A. Roberts and R. Guelff (eds), Documents on the Law of War (Oxford, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Rousseau, The State of War, in M. Forsyth, et al. (eds), The Theory of International Relations: Selected Texts from Gentili to Treitschke (London, 1970), p. 174.

    Google Scholar 

  34. E. Gellner, Thought and Change (London, 1964), ch. 7

    Google Scholar 

  35. Michael Mann, The Sources of Social Power, vol. 1 (Cambridge, 1986), esp. ch. 7.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  36. R.W. Cox, ‘Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory’, Millennium, 10, 1982, pp. 126–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. M. Hoffman, ‘Critical Theory and the Inter-Paradigm Debate’, Millennium, 15, 1987, pp. 231–49 focuses on Horkheimer and Habermas.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. A. Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations (London, 1990), chs 8–10, draws significantly on Hegel’s philosophical history.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  39. M. Herrera, ‘Equal Respect Among Unequal Partners: Gender Difference and the Constitution of Moral Subjects’, Philosophy East and West, 42, 1992, pp. 263–75. On the other hand, Hegel’s argument about the conflictual nature of international politics can be read as a gendered account of the states-system.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. R. Grant and K. Newland (eds), Gender and International Relations (Buckingham, 1991), esp. chs 1–3. For a discussion of Hegel’s impact on communitarian thought

    Google Scholar 

  41. S.A. Schwarzenbach, ‘Rawls, Hegel and Communitarianism’, Political Theory, vol. 19, 4, 1991, p. 540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. M. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge, 1982);

    Google Scholar 

  43. M. Walzer, Spheres of Justice (Oxford, 1983);

    Google Scholar 

  44. A. McIntyre, After Virtue (London, 1981).

    Google Scholar 

  45. H. Bull, ‘The State’s Positive Role in World Affairs’, Daedalus, 108, 1979, pp. 111–23.

    Google Scholar 

  46. T.H. Green, Prolegomena to Ethics (Oxford, 1906)

    Google Scholar 

  47. P.P. Nicholson, ‘Philosophical Idealism and International Politics: A Reply to Savigear’, British Journal of International Studies, vol. 2, 1976, pp. 76–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. T.H. Green, Prolegomena to Ethics (London, 1906).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 1996 Palgrave Macmillan, a division of Macmillan Publishers Limited

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Linklater, A. (1996). Hegel, the State and International Relations. In: Clark, I., Neumann, I.B. (eds) Classical Theories of International Relations. St Antony’s Series. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-24779-0_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics