Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 20))

  • 521 Accesses

Abstract

In (2014), Mark Sainsbury has claimed, first, that there is a variety of fiction operators, in particular the “according to f”- operator and the “in f”- operator, whose semantic contribution to the complex sentences they contribute to generate is different, and second, that no worlds-based semantical treatment works for any of them. In this paper, I want to hold that, when suitably reinterpreted, Sainsbury is utterly right as to his first claim, yet just partially right as to his second claim.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Sainsbury provides cases of further operators yet they are not fundamental for my present purposes, also because the issues some of them are meant to face can actually be dealt with in terms of the above operators. Cf. e.g. the “according to the early chapters of f”- and “it is clear by (some bits of) f”- operators.

  2. 2.

    Sainsbury’s original pair is “In War and Peace, there are both fictional and real characters” and “According to War and Peace, there are both fictional and real characters”. As I believe – cf. my Voltolini (2006b, 2013) – that fictional stories never contain real characters, but just surrogates of them (War and Peace for example does not contain the real Napoleon, but just a surrogate of his whose nature is ultimately fictional just as that of Prince Andrei), I have accordingly modified Sainsbury’s example. Yet nothing substantial hinges on that modification.

  3. 3.

    Cf. Walton (1990: 175, 177, 182).

  4. 4.

    As suggested by his (2009:41), where he rather says that according to the Holmes stories it is false that Holmes is a fictional detective.

  5. 5.

    For the scope of this paper, I accept Walton’s (1990) claim that there are make-believe games whose participants pretend that things unfold in a certain way. Yet nothing would substantially change if one appealed either to make-believe practices or even to make-believe mental processes, as I do e.g. in my Voltolini (2016).

  6. 6.

    Provided of course we allow for sets in our overall ontological domain.

  7. 7.

    In point of fact, I would say “always”, for as I said in fn.2, I believe that fictional stories are always constituted by fictional characters, some of which however are surrogates of real concrete individuals.

  8. 8.

    Notoriously, there are many problems as to whether a world of a make-believe game is a possible world and in the positive case, which possible world it is. For the purposes of this paper, I skip such problems.

  9. 9.

    Cf. Schiffer (1996, 2003). Evans (1982) labels the same use a conniving use.

  10. 10.

    Depending on one’s favorite semantic account of proper names, that sentence so used in such a context is either false or neither true nor false.

  11. 11.

    I hereby follow Predelli (2008), who according to me rightly thinks that the embedded sentence in isolation can only be fictionally true, as is claimed by the so-called context shift view that he himself defended in his (2005) (and that as to that sentence so taken I endorse as well: cf. Voltolini 2006a, 2016). Yet when things are conceived as I say in the text, the context-shift view as applied to the embedded sentence taken in isolation is clearly compatible with the account of the “according to f”-operator as a context shifter. As is well known, for Kaplan (1989), a context-shifter is a monster, yet for the reasons given in the text for the “according to f”-operator this is a welcome result, as Predelli himself holds. For more evidence, even outside fiction, of such context-shifting operators, cf. Schlenker (2003). Recanati (2000) avoids taking the operator as a context-shifter by framing it in a (more sophisticated) make-believe scope as well, the scope of what he calls a Meinongian or second-order pretense that involves both concrete individuals and fictional characters. Yet by so doing one gets that the relevant embedding sentence of the form “according to f, p” is again merely fictionally true, not really true as one wishes in conceiving it as a real comment on the fictionally used embedded sentence “p”.

  12. 12.

    I stick to this cautious formulation for in this paper, I do not want to be apriori ontologically committed to fictional characters. See below in the text.

  13. 13.

    Clearly enough, this is compatible with saying that such a proposition is true at that set, since something is true at a set iff it belongs to it. Cf. Jago (2015:598). Yet the proposition is such, not a sentence.

  14. 14.

    Cf. Voltolini (2006b).

  15. 15.

    In (2006b) I claimed that a sentence in its internal metafictional use is elliptical for a sentence of the form “In f, p”. For the purposes of this paper I remain neutral as to this claim.

  16. 16.

    Cf. Voltolini (2006b).See also my Voltolini (2011).

  17. 17.

    Hence, an antirealist has to reject a standard intensional reading of the “in f, p”- sentence, as I said in Voltolini (2011:104 fn.9).Incidentally, in taking a sentence such as (1) to be true, Sainsbury does not certainly want to be ontologically committed to fictional characters. For he is an antirealist about them (cf. his 2009).

  18. 18.

    Cf. Sainsbury (2014:280–8, particularly 287).

  19. 19.

    Cf. Kripke (1980:77).

  20. 20.

    For similar worries, cf. Voltolini (2006b:163–6).

  21. 21.

    For a clear formulation of this sense, cf. the following passage: “as far as literally fiction is concerned, the author is the authority. There is nothing else—e.g. reality, or other texts—towards which he is responsible. […] To read a text as a literary fiction is to decide not to look for any other justification over and above the text itself for the truth of the statements we read” (Santambrogio 1992:302; my translation). For the idea that fiction is something made up, cf. Deutsch (2000).

  22. 22.

    As some may know, this discovery prompted the Italian writer Pia Pera to write another story on the Humbert-Lolita affair that is recounted from Lolita’s own perspective: Lo’s Diary.

  23. 23.

    I have already defended the idea that some fiction-involving statements are analytic (an idea that to my knowledge was originally proposed by Bonomi 1979:46–8) in my Voltolini (2006b).

  24. 24.

    I thank Diego Marconi for some interesting discussions had with him on this paper’s topic.

References

  • Bonomi, A. (1979). Universi di discorso. Milan: Feltrinelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, H. (2000). “Making Up Stories,” in A. Everett and T. Hofweber (eds.), Empty Names, Fiction and the Puzzles of Non-existence. Stanford: CSLI Publications, 149–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jago, M. (2015). “Hyperintensional propositions”. Synthese 192: 585–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). “Demonstratives”. In J. Almog, J. Perry and H. Wettstein (eds.), Themes from Kaplan, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 481–563.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, S. (2005), Contexts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, S. (2008). “Modal Monsters and Talk about Fiction”. Journal of Philosophical Logic 37: 277–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2000). Oratio Obliqua, Oratio Recta. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, R.M. (2009). Fiction and Fictionalism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, R.M. (2014). “Fictional Worlds and Fiction Operators”. In M. García-Carpintero and G. Martí (eds.), Empty Representations, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 277–289.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Santambrogio, M. (1992). Forma e oggetto, Milan: Il Saggiatore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1996). “Language-Created Language-Independent Entities”. Philosophical Topics 24: 149–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (2003). The Things We Mean. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, P. (2003), “A Plea for Monsters”. Linguistic and Philosophy 26: 29–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2006a). “Fiction as a Base of Interpretation Contexts”. Synthese 153: 23–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2006b). How Ficta Follow Fiction. A Syncretistic Account of Fictional Entities. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2011). “How Creationism Supports for Kripke’s Vichianism on Fiction”. In F. Lihoreau (ed.), Truth in Fiction. Munich: OntosVerlag, 93–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2013). “Probably the Charterhouse of Parma does not exist, possibly not even that Parma”. Humana Mente 25: 235–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2016). “The Nature of Fiction/al Utterances”. Kairos 17: 28–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as Make Believe. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alberto Voltolini .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Voltolini, A. (2019). Varieties of Fiction Operators. In: Capone, A., Carapezza, M., Lo Piparo, F. (eds) Further Advances in Pragmatics and Philosophy: Part 2 Theories and Applications. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 20. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00973-1_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00973-1_11

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-00972-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-00973-1

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics