Skip to main content

Social Pathologies: Distinctive Features

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Imposed Rationality and Besieged Imagination

Part of the book series: Philosophy and Politics - Critical Explorations ((PPCE,volume 9))

Abstract

Social pathologies are presented as having four distinctive characteristics. Each of them is developed in different sections of this chapter.

  1. (a)

    Social pathologies are the effect of anonymous social processes, that is, they acquire a logic of their own that becomes independent of the participating agents, and therefore, it is not possible to attribute them to an agent or group of agents. Hence, social pathologies become independent from the agents that take part in it.

  2. (b)

    The second feature is the imposition of a type of practical rationality on a social space ruled by another type. This is so because there is a non-conscious transformation of the beliefs of the affected individuals who act in such a context, distorting the interpretation of its shared meaning.

  3. (c)

    The third one is the undermining of the agents’ autonomy, imagination and reflection. Undermining the imagination enables a type of rationality to be imposed on social spaces alien to it.

  4. (d)

    The fourth distinctive feature follows from the previous one, since one of the consequences of the weakening of imagination, autonomy and reflection is the stimulation of deceptive justifying processes, i.e., ideological processes.

Finally, I present “malinchism” as a particular case that illustrates social pathologies in the context of Latin American societies. Besides the undervalued self-image of Latin American people inherited from the Conquest and Colony that characterizes malinchism, it implies a methodological approach that can be projected to other specific cases equally affected by historical colonization.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Arendt presents a similar diagnosis of Modernity through what she calls “the rise of the social”, which among other features leads to replacing the action characteristic of political life with uniformed and conformist behaviour distinctive of “society”. This leads to a progressive loss of the quality of the political process and to a weakening of the state and government by the administration embodied in technocracy and bureaucracy (Arendt 1998: 40–43).

  2. 2.

    This is not only a concern of Critical Theory, but is also posed by Michael Walzer, who, through the concept of complex equality, aims to counteract those effects (Walzer 1983:17–20).

  3. 3.

    This process has been so pervasive and so prevalent in contemporary societies that even the contemporary attempt to reconceptualise modernity based on social acceleration cannot go beyond it (Rosa 2013). This concept, which provides an innovative perspective to explain late modernity, can be ultimately explained as an effect of the dynamics imposed by the institutionalisation of the means-ends rationality that, in becoming independent, also generates processes of social acceleration. Both the competition inherent to the economy, as well as the juridification that fosters it and the increasing imposition of technology on our daily lives, serve as the main drivers of the increasing complexity that leads to the aforementioned social acceleration (Rosa 2013), 73–6, (Rosa 2014): 26–7.

  4. 4.

    This process is presented in a very clear way by Adela Cortina, who at the same time illustrates the distortion of the practical context whose object is the good life, as a consequence of consumerism (Cortina 2002: 82–9).

  5. 5.

    The word “aporophobia” is based on the Greek word áporos, which means “poor” or “with no resources”. I introduce this term to refer to the rejection of poor people. In the Spanish-speaking world this word has been recently adopted as the result of the influence of philosopher Adela Cortina’s (2017) work.

  6. 6.

    This argument is inspired by the distinction introduced by Modzelewski (2017) between emotions towards a fact and emotions towards an object, according to which the latter emotions are desirable in social behaviour because they are triggered by the evaluation of someone’s actions, whereas the former are fixed in relation to a person who is the recipient of the emotion, no matter what this recipient does. Social discrimination is understood as coming from this type of emotions that do not evaluate doings, but beings (pp. 297–309).

  7. 7.

    Probably the best argument against monetarism understood in terms of tyranny has been presented by Michael Walzer through his concept of complex equality (1983: 17–21).

  8. 8.

    The discussion of exploitation is so dense and vast that it is impossible for this work to look into it comprehensively. I simply aim to introduce a possible causal explanation of individual attitudes from the perspective of social pathologies. An overview of the problem can be found in Nielsen and Ware (1997).

  9. 9.

    Honneth and Barber agree in this point, though the second does not use the concept of social pathologies (Barber 2007: 117–13; Honneth 2009: 29).

  10. 10.

    Juan Fló makes a distinction between two ways of understanding ideology: one that provides a social group with a vision of the world, which therefore articulates its self-understanding and interests, and another one that is misleading and deceptive at the service of certain social and class interests, which he calls “ideological alienation.” This second form of ideology coincides with the deceptive justification I refer to (Fló 1967: 81–82). A similar distinction has been addressed by Geuss (1981: 15–22) as ideology in descriptive and pejorative senses.

  11. 11.

    This position is compatible with an interpretation of the growing role that justification has had in Cohen’s work. In a 1968’s early article entitled “The workers and the word”, he states that “(…)

    for all classes except, as we shall see, the working class, the fact that a gap exists between them and other classes means that they must lose contact with the truth if they are to develop a theory which will further their interests” (Cohen 2014: 276). In “Freedom, justice and capitalism” he argues that the clarifying role of justification, in particular philosophical justification, functions as a “powerful solvent for at least some ideological illusions” (1988: 291). Later he introduces the ideas of “comprehensive justification” and “justifying community”, which Cohen supposes absent in the talented that demand greater wages from the same productivity, (2008: 41–67) and that implies, to a certain extent, a functional failure that can be understood as blocking justification.

  12. 12.

    I understand the guide for the intervention in societies from Apel’s part B of the discourse ethics, which provides a principle of responsibility. This commitment to responsibility constitutes the end (telos) to ensure the conditions of possibility for resolving conflicts discursively, that is, as established by the principle of universalisation that Habermas refers to as ‘U’. It implies guaranteeing that people can take part in dialogue by giving reasons to justify their positions (Apel 1993: 28).

  13. 13.

    Mario Sambarino (1980) has presented a systematic argumentation to rule out any possible essentialism referring to Latin America’s identity, tradition and authenticity.

References

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 1972. Beitrag zur Ideologienlehre. In Gesammelte Schriften 8, ed. I. Soziologische Schriften, 457–477. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apel, Karl-Otto. 1993. How to Ground a Universalistic Ethics of Co-responsibility for the Effects of Collective Actions and Activities. Philosophica 52 (2): 9–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Types of Rationality Today: The Continuum of Reason Between Science and Ethics. In Selected Essays. Volume Two. Ethics and the Theory of Rationality, ed. Eduardo Mendieta, 137–173. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1998. The Human Condition. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barber, Benjamin. 2007. Consumed: How Markets Corrupt Children, Infantilize Adults, and Swallow Citizens Whole. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, Seyla. 2002. The Claims of Culture: Equality and Diversity in the Global Era. Princeton/Woodstock: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boltanski, Luc. 2011. On Critique: A Sociology of Emancipation. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Celikates, Robin. 2006. From Critical Social Theory to a Social Theory of Critique: On the Critique of Ideology After the Pragmatic Turn. Constellations 13 (1): 21–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, David A. 2012. Adaptation, Poverty and Development Contents: They Dynamics of Subjective Well-Being. Houndmills/Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Gerald A. 1988. Freedom, Justice and Capitalism. In History, Labour and Freedom. Themes from Marx, 286–304. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. The Workers and the Word: Why Marx Had the Right to Think He Was Right. In Lectures on the History of Moral and Political Philosophy, ed. Jonathan Wolff, 268–283. Princeton/Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cortina, Adela. 2002. Por una ética del consumo. Madrid: Taurus.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Aporofobia, el rechazo al pobre. Barcelona: Paidós.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cortina, Adela, and Gustavo Pereira. 2009. Pobreza y libertad. Erradicar la pobreza desde el enfoque de las capacidades de Amartya Sen. Madrid: Tecnos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Echeverría, Bolívar. 1997. El dinero y el objeto del deseo. In Las ilusiones de la Modernidad, 74–82. México: UNAM-El equilibrista.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, Jon. 1983. Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality. Paris/Cambridge: Maison des Sciences de l’Homme-Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Ulysses Unbound. Studies in Rationality, Precommitment, and Constraints. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Explaining Social Behavior: More nuts and bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martínez Estrada, Ezequiel. 1991 [1933]. Radiografía de la Pampa. Madrid: Archivo CSIC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fló, Juan. 1967. La alienación ideológica. In Alcance y formas de la alienación, Juan Fló and Mario Sambarino, 61–95. Montevideo: Biblioteca de Cultura Universitaria.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forst, Rainer. 2002. Contexts of justice: Political Philosophy beyond Liberalism and Communitarianism. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Noumenal power. The Journal of Political Philosophy 23 (2): 111–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. The right to justification: Elements of a constructivist theory of justice. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, Hans Georg. 1989. Truth and Method. Second revised edition. Trans. Rev. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall. London/New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geuss, Raymond. 1981. The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1987. The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 2. Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason. Trans. Thomas McCarthy. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990a. Discursive Ethics: Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justification. In Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Trans. Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen, 43–115. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990b. Morality and Ethical Life: Does Hegel’s Critique of Kant Apply to Discourse Ethics? In Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, 195–215. New York: Wiley .

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 1995. The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. A Social Pathology of Reason: On the Intellectual Legacy of Critical Theory. Trans. James Ingram et al., 19–42. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Freedom’s Right: The Social Foundations of Democratic Life. Trans. Joseph Ganahl. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. 2002. Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Trans. Edmund Jephcott. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaeggi, Rahel. 2009. Rethinking Ideology. In New Waves in Political Philosophy, ed. Boudewijn De Bruin and Christopher Zurn, 63–86. Houdmills/Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, Hans. 1984. The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leyva, Gustavo. 2017. Filosofía política en América Latina. In Filosofía iberoamericana del siglo XX, II. Filosofía práctica y Filosofía de la cultura. Enciclopedia Iberoamericana de Filosofía, ed. Manuel Reyes Mate, León Olivé, and Osvaldo Guariglia, vol. 33, 377–440. Madrid: Trotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lukács, Georg. 1971. Reification and the Consciousmess of the Proletariat. In History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics. Trans. Rodney Livingstone, 83–333. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mariátegui, José Carlos. 1970 [1928]. Siete ensayos de interpretación de la realidad peruana. Montevideo: Biblioteca de Marcha.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. 1975. The German Ideology. Vol. 1, Critique of Modern German Philosophy According to its Representatives Feuerbach, B. Bauer and Stirner. In Marx/Engels Collected Works, Volume 5 Marx and Engels 1845–1847, 19–451.

    Google Scholar 

  • Modzelewski, Helena. 2013. Narrative as an Educational Factor for Human Development: A Case Study with Homeless Single Mothers in Uruguay. In Education, Economics and Development, ed. Suzanne Majhanovich and Macleans A. Geo-Jaja, 143–158. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Emociones, educación y democracia: una proyección de la teoría de las emociones de Martha Nussbaum. México: Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas-UNAM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molyneux, Maxine. 2006. Mothers at the Service of the New Poverty Agenda: Progresa/Oportunidades, Mexico’s Conditional Transfer Programme. Social Policy & Administration 40 (4): 425–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, Kai, and Robert Ware, eds. 1997. Exploitation. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paz, Octavio. 1985. The Sons of La Malinche. In The Laberynth of Solitude and Other Writings. Trans. Lysander Kemp, Yara Milos, and Rschel Philips Belash, 65–88. New York: Grove Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereira, Gustavo. 2013. Elements of a Critical Theory of Justice. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pereira, Gustavo, and Andrea Vigorito, eds. 2010. Preferencias adaptativas: Entre deseos, frustración y logros. Montevideo: Fin de Siglo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosa, Hartmut. 2013. Social Acceleration. A New Theory of Modernity. Columbia: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Alienation and acceleration. Towards a critical theory of late-modern temporality. Copenhaguen: NSU Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sambarino, Mario. 1980. Identidad, tradición y autenticidad. Tres problemas de América Latina. Caracas: Centro de Estudios Latinoamericanos Rómulo Gallegos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saviano, Roberto. 2007. Gomorrah: A Personal Journey into the Violent International Empire of Naples’ Organized Crime System. New York: Picador-Farrar, Strauss and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shklar, Judith. 1990. The Faces of Injustice. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel, Georg. 2004. The Philosophy of Money. Trans. Tom Bottomore and David Frisby. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich, Keith E. 2011. Rationality and the reflective mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2003. Why Societies Need Dissent. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1985. The politics of recognition. In Philosophical arguments, 225–256. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veraza, Jorge. 2008. Subsunción real del consumo al capital. Itaca: Dominación fisiológica y psicológica en la sociedad contemporánea.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villatoro, Pablo. 2005. Los programas de protección social asistencial en América Latina y sus impactos en las familias: algunas reflexiones. Políticas hacia las familias, protección e inclusión social. Santiago: CEPAL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vohs, Kathleen D., Nicole L. Mead, and Miranda R. Goode. 2006. The Psychological Consequences of Money. Science 314 (5802): 1154–1156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael. 1983. Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1978. Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. London/New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zajonc, Robert B. 1968. Attitudinal Effects of Mere Exposure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 68 (1): 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Mere Exposure: A Gateway to the Subliminal. Currents Directions in Psychological Science 10 (6): 224–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Pereira, G. (2019). Social Pathologies: Distinctive Features. In: Imposed Rationality and Besieged Imagination. Philosophy and Politics - Critical Explorations, vol 9. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-26520-5_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics