Skip to main content

Descartes and Active Perception

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Active Perception in the History of Philosophy

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 14))

Abstract

There is considerable textual evidence in Descartes’ Meditations that suggests he held the human perceiver to be passive during sense-perception—that is, the perceiver plays no active role in accomplishing such sensory perception. In this paper, I argue that the Cartesian human perceiver does play an active role in accomplishing her own sense-perceptions.

The paper begins by pointing to Descartes’ Meditations, which strongly suggests that he thought that sensory perception is passive. I then elucidate the sense(s) in which the Cartesian perceiver might be passive, given Descartes’ adherence to mind-body dualism. Finally, I argue, on the basis of texts external to the Meditations, that Descartes did not in fact hold that the perceiver is passive.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Descartes (1962, 1984/1985, 1991).

  2. 2.

    For Descartes, such sensory perceptions are to be distinguished from acts of the imagination. While he thinks that both can only take place with a physical body, cases of imagination, e.g. in dreams and hallucinations, have their distal cause within the perceiver’s own body. In contrast, sensory perception has its distal cause outside the thinker’s body and involves the relevant sensory organs such as the eyes, nose etc. Descartes also distinguishes between acts of imagination that involve the will, and “passive” imagination (e.g. in dreams) that do not. (AT 11:344–5, CSM 1:336).

  3. 3.

    As mentioned, in order for sensory perception to take place, the causal chain for such perception must originate from outside the perceiver’s body.

  4. 4.

    As various commentators have pointed out, Descartes’ distinction between action and passion here is derived from Aristotle. See, e.g., Hoffman (1990); Schickel (2011).

  5. 5.

    Shapiro (2003, p. 38).

  6. 6.

    See, for example, Hoffman (1990).

  7. 7.

    Normore and Brown (2003, p. 92).

  8. 8.

    Normore and Brown (2003, p. 93).

  9. 9.

    Indeed, some writers have held that Descartes thinks that it is such qualia that are directly perceived by the senses. They suggest that it is from our direct sensory perception of these qualities that we infer that there are finite substances like minds and matter in which they inhere. Such writers would include Vinci (1993); Wee (2002, 2006).

  10. 10.

    For Descartes, items like the wax, towers or statues are not of course themselves substances. For Descartes, there are in the created universe only two kinds of substances—finite minds and extended matter.

  11. 11.

    See, for example, Aristotle’s De Anima, 2:12 424a17. Note that the passive reception of forms for Aristotle does not in the first instance take place in the mind, but (arguably) in the relevant sense-organ. (Aristotle did not of course hold on to the dualism of mind and matter–or at least not in the way that Descartes did. For a solid discussion of this issue, see Wilkes (1992).

  12. 12.

    Kenny (1968, p. 123).

  13. 13.

    Descartes would of course hold that these third-grade sensory judgments of the intellect can then be followed by judgments of the will (i.e., by affirmations and denials by the will).

  14. 14.

    I would like to thank Annette Baier and C.L. Ten for their helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

Bibliography

Primary Sources

  • Descartes, R. (1962). C. Adam & P. Tanneryeds (Eds.), Oeuvres de Descartes (Vols. 1–12). Paris: Vrin (cited as AT, followed by Volume no. and page no.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1984/1985). J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch (Eds.), The philosophical writings of Descartes (Vols. 1–2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (cited as CSM 1 and CSM 2, followed by page no.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1991). J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D. Murdoch, & A. Kenny (Eds.), The philosophical writings of Descartes (Vol. 3). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (cited as CSMK, followed by page no.).

    Google Scholar 

Secondary Sources

  • Hoffman, P. (1990). Cartesian passions and Cartesian dualism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 71, 301–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A. (1968). Descartes: A study of his philosophy. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Normore, C., & Brown, D. (2003). Traces of the body: Cartesian passions. In B. Williston & A. Gombay (Eds.), Passion and virtue in Descartes (pp. 83–106). Amherst: Humanity Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schickel, J. A. (2011). Descartes in the identity of action and passion. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 19, 1067–1084.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2003). The structure of the passions of the soul and the soul-body union. In B. Williston & A. Gombay (Eds.), Passion and virtue in Descartes (pp. 31–79). Amherst: Humanity Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vinci, T. (1993). Cartesian truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wee, C. (2002). Descartes’ two proofs of the external world. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 80(4), 487–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wee, C. (2006). Material falsity and error in Descartes’ meditations. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkes, K. V. (1992). Psuchē vs the mind. In M. C. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on aristotle’s de Anima (pp. 27–56). Oxford: Clarendon press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cecilia Wee .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wee, C. (2014). Descartes and Active Perception. In: Silva, J., Yrjönsuuri, M. (eds) Active Perception in the History of Philosophy. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 14. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-04361-6_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics