Skip to main content

The “Doctrine of Principles” in Neo-Constitutional Theories and the Principle of Reasonableness in Action

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
General Principles of Law - The Role of the Judiciary

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 46))

  • 1781 Accesses

Abstract

The application of legal principles in legal argument is a fundamental claim of the neo-constitutionalist legal theory. Principles are at the top of the legal hierarchy and provide for the material unity of the judicial system, which is a pluralistic one and intertwined with various needs. Consequently, principles are to be regarded as prior and antecedent to rules, from a pre-political, fundamental point of view aiming at the judicialization of power. Considering the expansive nature of principles, in particular constitutional principles and principles proclaimed by supranational Charters of rights, it is no longer sufficient to respect the law’s prescriptions about who and how: gradually, and mostly thanks to the control of constitutional legitimacy, an unavoidable question is arising about the what of law, the an of legal rulings as well as its compatibility with the standards of justice. Dworkin, in particular, affirms that principles are first of all “a requirement of justice or fairness or some other dimension of morality”; they rightly step into the world of law thanks to the adequacy and to the justification power they show. The first part of the present chapter will analyze the definitive recognition of the normative character of principles; in particular the difference of their structure and functioning from rules, and finally the different and similar aspects between principles and values. The second part of the chapter will observe more closely the functioning of principle of reasonableness, through the analysis of some passages of important judgments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Dworkin (1978, 1985, 1986, 1996); Habermas (1992, ed. Ceppa 2001); Alexy (1992a, 1994); Nino (1994).

  2. 2.

    For an overall view on the concept of “principle”, see Dworkin ( 1978 ); Pattaro (1987), pp. 25–35; Betti (1971); Del Vecchio (1958), p. 205 ff.; Alpa (2006); Cheng (1953); Guastini (2004), pp. 199–205. See also I principi generali del diritto, Atti del convegno, Accademia dei Lincei, Roma, 1992 and conference proceedings of VIII World Congress of the International Association of Constitutional Law, Mexico City, 2010, available at: http://www.juridicas.unam.mx/wccl/en/i.htm.

  3. 3.

    See Barberis (2011), pp. 33–41; Mazzarese (2002); Pozzolo (2001); Omaggio (2003), pp. 93–131; La Torre (2010); Bongiovanni (1999).

  4. 4.

    The wording is of Mario Dogliani, quoted in Omaggio (2003), p. 108, footnote 44 (my translation).

  5. 5.

    Pizzorusso (2011), p. 658; Guastini (2010), p. 328; Alpa (2006), p. 263.

  6. 6.

    Hart (1961) (eds. Bullock and Raz 1994).

  7. 7.

    Dworkin (1978), p. 22.

  8. 8.

    Dworkin (2011).

  9. 9.

    Habermas (1992) (ed. Ceppa 2001), p. 17; Habermas (1996), Italian partial version (my translation).

  10. 10.

    Alexy (1994, 2000).

  11. 11.

    For the technique of balancing see Alexy (1992b), pp. 153–192; Alexy (2007), pp. 45–56; Dworkin (1978); Celano ( 2002), pp. 223–239; Pino ( 2009), pp. 131–158; Pino (2007); Bin (1992); Modugno (1995), pp. 643–648; Contra Waldron (1993); Ferrajoli ( 2013); Alexander and Kress (1995).

  12. 12.

    See Atienza and Ruiz Manero (1996, 1998).

  13. 13.

    MacCormick (1978), p. 245.

  14. 14.

    Rawls (1971), p. 18.

  15. 15.

    MacCormick (1978), p. 234.

  16. 16.

    Habermas (1996), p. 258.

  17. 17.

    Habermas (2001), p. 36 (my translation).

  18. 18.

    Habermas (1996), p. 255.

  19. 19.

    See also Amirante (1981), p. 9 ff. and  Baldassarre (1991), p. 639 ff.

  20. 20.

    Zagrebelsky (2002), p. 872.

  21. 21.

    Dworkin (1978), p. 91.

  22. 22.

    Spartan Steel & Alloys Ltd v. Martin&Co. (Contractors) Ltd., 3 All ER 557 (1972). See also Shiner (2005), pp. 47–48.

  23. 23.

    See Gordley et al. (2006), pp. 313–314.

  24. 24.

    Dworkin (1978), p. 108.

  25. 25.

    MacCormick (1978), p. 263 (emphasis in the original).

  26. 26.

    Ibid., p. 264.

  27. 27.

    Dworkin (1985).

  28. 28.

    See also Nino (1991a, b).

  29. 29.

    Hart (1979), p. 22.

  30. 30.

    See Palombella (2006), p. 147 ff.

  31. 31.

    Sen (1985), p. 12.

  32. 32.

    Palombella (2002), p. 155 (my translation).

  33. 33.

    See “I principi di proporzionalità e ragionevolezza nella giurisprudenza costituzionale, anche in rapporto alla giurisprudenza delle Corti europee”, in “Quaderno predisposto in occasione dell’incontro trilaterale tra Corte Costituzionale italiana, Tribunale Costituzionale spagnolo e Corte Costituzionale portoghese”, pp. 32–34, available at:

    http://www.cortecostituzionale.it/documenti/convegni_seminari/RI_QuadernoStudi_Roma2013.pdf. See also Atienza (1990), pp. 148–161. On “reasonableness” in general as interpretation and application technique see Perelman (1979); Aarnio (1987); Corten (1999), pp. 613–625.

  34. 34.

    Viola (2000), pp. 35–71 (my translation).

  35. 35.

    Luther (2007)  “Ragionevolezza e dignità umana”, In La ragionevolezza nella ricerca scientifica ed il suo ruolo specifico nel sapere giuridico, ed. Augusto Cerri, 185-214. Roma: Aracne p. 3,

    (my translation).

  36. 36.

    Alexy (1994), p. 297 (my translation).

  37. 37.

    Italian Constitutional Court, judgment no. 220 of 1995, Considerato in diritto, para. 4.

  38. 38.

    MacCormick ( 1978), p. 132.

  39. 39.

    Dworkin (1986), pp. 263–274.

  40. 40.

    Italian Constitutional Court, judgment no. 249 of  2010.

  41. 41.

    Ibid., para. 9.

  42. 42.

    Ibid., para. 4(1).

  43. 43.

    Italian Constitutional Court, judgment no. 104 of 1969 (my translation).

  44. 44.

    Italian Constitutional Court, judgment no. 148 of 2008 (my translation).

  45. 45.

    Dworkin (1978), p. 130.

  46. 46.

    Italian Constitutional Court, judgment no. 249 of 2010, para. 5.

  47. 47.

    Della Cananea (2009), p. 25 (my translation).

  48. 48.

    Case C-61/11 PPU El Dridi [2011] ECR I-3015.

  49. 49.

    See Klatt and Meister (2012).

  50. 50.

    Directive 2008/115/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council on common standards and procedures in Member States for returning illegally staying third-country nationals, Strasbourg (16 December 2008).

  51. 51.

    Unlike illegal immigrants, who do not have valid documents, citizens in illegal stay might have entered a “guest” Country legally and later have lost the legal requirements, mostly when their residence permits expire and are not renewed.

  52. 52.

    El Dridi cit., para. 54.

  53. 53.

    Ibid., pp. 3048–3049, para. 43 (emphasis added).

  54. 54.

    Ibid., p. 3052, para. 55.

  55. 55.

    Zanichelli (2004), p. 46 (my translation).

  56. 56.

    Case Relating to Certain Aspects of the Laws on the Use of Languages in Education in Belgium (App. nos. 1474/62; 1677/62; 1691/62; 1769/63; 1994/63; 2126/64), ECtHR, judgment of 23 July 1968.

  57. 57.

    On this case, and on the protection of minority languages, see Torretta (2014), pp. 695–734.

  58. 58.

    It is well known, though, that the “prohibition of discrimination”, which is related to the principle of formal equality, does not completely cover the concept of “protection of minorities”. The latter is closer to the principle of substantial equality, which requires “positive discriminations” and “affirmative actions”. See Guiglia (2012), p. 8. See also D’Aloia (2002), p. 434.

  59. 59.

    Case Relating to Certain Aspects of the Laws on the Use of Languages in Education in Belgium cit., para. 10 (emphasis added).

  60. 60.

    Lauterpacht observed on this matter: “[W]hen, in international disputes, rules of general jurisprudence are referred to, what is meant is that not a rule of one particular system of private law is to be applied, but only such a rule … as has gained recognition by the general body of civilized nations. This is so for the simple reason that international law has not, in the particular sphere, developed any rules on its own. In fact, there would be no need to have recourse to general jurisprudence, if there were international rule already at hand”. Lauterpacht (1975), p. 206.

  61. 61.

    Case Relating to Certain Aspects of the Laws on the Use of Languages in Education in Belgium cit., para. 10.

  62. 62.

    Ibid., para. 5 (emphasis added).

  63. 63.

    Ruggeri (2000), pp. 567–611.

  64. 64.

    On the concept of “public” in law, that is to say on a conception of law viewed as the foundation of the public dimension beyond States, see Palombella (2012), Chap. V.

  65. 65.

    Kingsbury et al. (2005); Cassese (2006), pp. 663–694; D’Alterio (2010). See also the works of the “GAL” Project, available at: http://www.iilj.org/GAL/.

  66. 66.

    Brown (2008).

  67. 67.

    With regard to this point, judge Cançado Trindade offered a particularly pertinent observation about the International Court of Justice. He asserted: “[T]he Hague Court, also known as the World Court, is not simply the International Court of Law, it is the International Court of Justice, and, as such, it cannot overlook principles” (emphasis in the original). See Pulp Mills on the River Uruguay (Argentina v. Uruguay) [2010] ICJ Rep. 14. The quote is taken from Fontanelli (2012), pp. 119–136.

References

  • Aarnio, Aulis. 1987. T he Rational as Reasonable: A Treatise on Legal Justification, ed. Alan Mabe. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, Larry, and Ken Kress. 1995. Against Legal Principles. In Law and Interpretation, ed. Andrei Marmor, 279-327. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, Robert. 1992a. Begriff und Geltung des Rechts. Frankfurt, New York: Campus Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, Robert. 1992b. Rights, Legal Reasoning and Rational Discourse. Ratio Juris 5: 143-152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, Robert. 1994. Theorie der Grundrechte. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, Robert. 2000. On the Structure of Legal Principles. Ratio Juris 13: 294-304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, Robert. 2005. La formula per la quantificazione del peso nel bilanciamento. Ars Interpretandi,10: 92-123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, Robert. 2007. Diritti fondamentali, bilanciamento e razionalità. Ars interpretandi 12: 131-144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alpa, Guido. 2006. I principi generali. Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amirante, Carlo. 1981. La Costituzione come “sistema di valori” e la trasformazione dei diritti fondamentali nella giurisprudenza della Corte Costituzionale tedesca. Politica del diritto 1: 9-70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atienza, Manuel, and Juan Ruiz Manero. 1990. On the Reasonable in Law. Ratio Juris 3,1 bis: 148-161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atienza, Manuel, and Juan Ruiz Manero. 1996. Las piezas del derecho. Teoría de los enunciados jurídicos. Barcelona: Ariel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atienza, Manuel, and Juan Ruiz Manero. 1998. A Theory of Legal Sentences. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldassarre, Antonio. 1991. Costituzione e teoria dei valori. Politica del diritto 4: 639-658.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberis, Mauro. 2011. Manuale di filosofia del diritto. Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Betti, Emilio. 1971. Interpretazione della legge e degli atti giuridici. Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bin, Roberto. 1992. Diritti e argomenti. Il bilanciamento degli interessi nella giurisprudenza costituzionale. Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bongiovanni, Giorgio. 1999. La teoria “costituzionalistica” del diritto di Ronald Dworkin. In Filosofi del diritto contemporanei, ed. Gianfrancesco Zanetti, 247-285. Milano: Raffaello Cortina Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Chester. 2008. The Cross-Fertilization of Principles Relating to Procedure and Remedies in the Jurisprudence of International Courts and Tribunals. Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review 30: 219-246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Celano, Bruno. 2002. “Defeasibility” e bilanciamento. Sulla possibilità di revisioni stabili. Ragion Pratica 18: 223-239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassese, Sabino. 2006. Administrative Law without the State? The Challenge of Global Regulation. New York University Journal of International Law and Politics 37/4: 663-694.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, Bin. 1953. General Principles of Law as Applied by International Courts and Tribunals. London: Stevens & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corten, Olivier. 1999. The Notion of “Reasonable” in International Law: Legal Discourse, Reason and Contradictions. The International and Comparative Law Quarterly. 48/3: 613-625.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Aloia, Antonio. 2002. Eguaglianza sostanziale e diritto diseguale. Contributo allo studio delle azioni positive nella prospettiva costituzionale. Padova: Cedam.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Alterio, Elisa. 2010. La funzione di regolazione delle Corti nello spazio giuridico globale. Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald M. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald M. 1985. A Matter of Principle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald M. 1986. Law’s Empire. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald M. 1996. Freedom of Law. The Moral Reading of the America Constitution, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald M. 2011. Justice for Hedgehogs. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Del Vecchio, Giorgio. 1958 [1921]. Sui principi generali del diritto. Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Della Cananea, Giacinto. 2009. Al di là dei confini statuali. Principi generali del diritto pubblico globale. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrajoli, Luigi. 2013. La democrazia attraverso i diritti. Roma, Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fontanelli, Filippo. 2012. The Invocation of the Exception of Non-Performance: A Case-Study on the Role and Application of General Principles of International Law of Contractual Origin. Cambridge Journal of International and Comparative Law 1: 119–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordley, James, and Arthur Taylor von Meheren. 2006. An Introduction to Comparative Study of Private Law. Readings, Cases, Materials. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini, Renato. 2004. L’interpretazione dei documenti normativi. Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini, Renato. 2010. Le fonti del diritto. Fondamenti teorici. Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guiglia, Giovanni. 2012. Non discriminazione ed uguaglianza: unite nella diversità. http://www.gruppodipisa.it/wp-content/uploads/2012/05/guiglia.pdf.

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between Facts and Norms. Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Trans. William Rehg. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen (ed. Leonardo Ceppa). 2001 [1992]. Diritto, morale, politica. Torino: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, L. A. Herbert. 1979. Tra utilità e diritti. Sociologia del diritto 6/1-2: 1-22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, L. A. Herbert (eds. Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz). 1994 [1961]. The Concept of Law. With a Postscript. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingsbury, Benedict, Nico Krisch, and Richard B. Stewart. 2005. The Emergence of Global Administrative Law. Law and Contemporary Problems 68: 15-62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klatt, Matthias, and Moritz Meister. 2012. The Constitutional Structure of Proportionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • La Torre, Massimo. 2010. Dopo Hart: il dibattito giusfilosofico contemporaneo. In Prospettive di filosofia del diritto del nostro tempo, Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lauterpacht, Hersch. 1975. International Law: Being the Collected Papers of Hersch Lauterpacht. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luther, Joerg. 2007. Ragionevolezza e dignità umana. In La ragionevolezza nella ricerca scientifica ed il suo ruolo specifico nel sapere giuridico, ed. Augusto Cerri, 185-214. Roma: Aracne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazzarese, Tecla (ed.). 2002. Neocostituzionalismo e tutela (sovra)nazionale dei diritti fondamentali. Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, Neil. 1978. Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Modugno, Franco. 1995. Chiosa a chiusa. Un modello di bilanciamento di valori. Giurisprudenza italiana 1: 643-648.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nino, Carlos. 1991a. The Ethics of Human Rights. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nino, Carlos. 1991b. The Epistemological Moral Relevance of Democracy. Ratio Juris 4/1: 36-51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nino, Carlos. 1994. Derecho, moral y politica. Una revisión de la teoría general del derecho. Barcelona: Ariel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Omaggio, Vincenzo. 2003. Teorie dell’interpretazione. Napoli: Editoriale Scientifica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palombella, Gianluigi. 2002. L’autorità dei diritti. Roma, Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palombella, Gianluigi. 2006. Dopo la certezza. Il diritto in equilibrio tra giustizia e democrazia. Bari: Dedalo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palombella, Gianluigi. 2012. È possibile una legalità globale? Il Rule of Law e la governance del mondo. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattaro, Enrico. 1987. Alle origini della nozione “principi generali del diritto”. In Soggetto e principi generali del diritto, ed. Maurizio Basciu, 25-66. Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, Chaim. 1979. The Rational and Reasonable. In The New Rhetoric and the Humanistics: Essays on Rhetoric and its Application, ed. Chaim Perelman, 117-123. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pino, Giorgio. 2007. Conflitto e bilanciamento tra diritti fondamentali. Una mappa dei problemi. Ragion Pratica 28: 219-273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pino, Giorgio. 2009. Principi e argomentazione giuridica. Ars interpretandi 14: 131-160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pizzorusso, Alessandro. 2011. Delle fonti del diritto: art. 1-9. Bologna: Zanichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pozzolo, Susanna. 2001. Neocostituzionalismo e positivismo giuridico. Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruggeri, Antonio. 2000. Ragionevolezza e valori, attraverso il prisma della giustizia costituzionale. Diritto e società 4: 567-611.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya. 1985. Rights as Goals. In Equality and Discrimination: Essays in Freedom and Justice, eds. Stephen Guest and Alan Milne, 11-25. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiner, A. Roger. 2005. Legal Institutions and Sources of Law. In A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence, eds. Enrico Pattaro, Giovanni Sartor, Hubert Rottleuthner and Aleksander Peczenik. vol. III. Dordrecht, Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torretta, Paola. 2014. I diritti delle minoranze linguistiche e il “primato” della cittadinanza europea. Diritto pubblico comparato ed europeo 2: 695-734.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viola, Francesco. 2000. Costituzione e ragione pubblica: il principio di ragionevolezza tra diritto e politica. Persona y Derecho 46/1: 35-71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 1993. Liberal Rights. Collected papers 1981-1991. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagrebelsky, Gustavo. 2002. Diritto per: valori, principi, o regole? A proposito della dottrina dei principi di Ronald Dworkin. Quaderni fiorentini per la storia del pensiero giuridico moderno 31: 865-897.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zanichelli, Maria. 2004. Il discorso sui diritti. Un atlante teorico. Padova: Cedam.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Francesco De Vanna .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

De Vanna, F. (2015). The “Doctrine of Principles” in Neo-Constitutional Theories and the Principle of Reasonableness in Action. In: Pineschi, L. (eds) General Principles of Law - The Role of the Judiciary. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 46. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-19180-5_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics