Skip to main content

Conceptual Relativity in Philosophy

  • Chapter
A Pluralist Theory of the Mind

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 2))

  • 660 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter discusses arguments for conceptual relativity and their philosophical implications. I start with the ideal of exactly one fundamental ontology as it is common in analytic metaphysics. Contemporary metaphysicians often try to step behind the plurality of ordinary ontologies by employing a distinction between “ordinary” and “fundamental” existence questions. While we use a wide range of ontologies in ordinary and scientific contexts, the goal of metaphysicians is to evaluate what exists in the most fundamental sense. Conceptual relativists like Putnam and Hirsch reject the metaphysical appeal to exactly one fundamental ontology and therefore endorse a substantive conceptual pluralism. I consider a range of arguments for conceptual relativity that are based on considerations of understandability (“we do not even understand claims about a supposedly fundamental ontology”) and epistemic access (“we could never figure out what entities fundamentally exist”). While I endorse conceptual relativity, I acknowledge that debates about these arguments usually end in an intellectual stalemate. I therefore propose to shift attention from conceptual relativity in philosophical thought experiments to conceptual relativity in scientific practice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    One interesting area of research that is concerned with similarities and differences between folk ontologies is ethnobiology. Berlin (1992) and Atran and Medin (2008) provide helpful overviews for research on cross-cultural issues in folk-biological ontologies. See Ludwig (2015) for a detailed discussion.

  2. 2.

    The relation between “metaphysics” and “ontology” is a complicated issue due to the vagueness of both terms. I will follow a common use of both terms by considering metaphysics to be generally concerned with the structure of reality and ontology to be concerned more specifically with issues of existence. Even if this distinction is often important, Putnam’s argument from conceptual relativity clearly combines both issues by rejecting the ideal of exactly one fundamental ontology on the basis of a general rejection of the ideal of one fundamental account of reality.

  3. 3.

    Most famously Quine (1948, 21); cf. Chalmers (2009, 77). See Guarino et al. (2009) for the wide range of uses of “ontology” in philosophy and science.

  4. 4.

    Sellars (1963, 62–75); Unger (1979); van Inwagen (1990, 81–97); Merricks (2001) are influential positions that challenge ordinary objects in one way or another. Unger (2005), however, has abandoned his eliminativism about macrophysical objects.

  5. 5.

    Eklund (2013) argues that Carnap-references in contemporary metaphysics are largely based on a misunderstanding of this historical debate.

  6. 6.

    Chalmers’ (2009, 80–85) proposes an analogous distinction between ordinary and ontological existence questions. “Ontological existence questions” in the sense of Chalmers are exclusively concerned with fundamental ontological truths and therefore correspond to my “fundamental existence questions”.

  7. 7.

    This strategy is spelled out by Van Inwagen (1990, 98–114). See Thomasson (2007) for a critical discussion.

  8. 8.

    Putnam’s criticism of Ontology with a capital “O” occasionally leads him to an anti-ontological rhetoric as illustrated by the title of his Ethics without Ontology (2004 cf. Pihlström 2006 and Copp 2006). Dale (2008) extends this strategy to debates about mind and cognition by suggesting a “cognitive science without ontology”. However, I do not assume that Putnam’s or Dale’s proposals are incompatible with my presentation of ontological pluralism. Instead, the difference is largely rhetorical: while I talk about “ontology” in a metaphysically shallow sense that is ubiquitous in scientific practice, Putnam and Dale reject “Ontology” as a philosophical project that aims at exactly one fundamental account of what exists.

  9. 9.

    Dorr and Rosen (2002) provide a helpful overview. See Tallant (2014) for a (critical) discussion of nihilism and Van Cleve (2008) for a defense of universalism.

  10. 10.

    Compare Rosen and Dorr (2002) and Bennett (2009) who raise these issues but do not consider them conclusive arguments against the ideal of one fundamental ontology.

  11. 11.

    One may also worry that philosophical intuitions about the understandability or non-understandability of metaphysical issues are easy prey for the “negative program” in experimental philosophy (Alexander et al. 2010; cf. Thomasson 2012) that challenges the use of intuitions in philosophical arguments. If there are no good arguments of why we should consider certain metaphysical issues understandable or not understandable, the variability of intuitions provides a further reason to expect a stalemate in the discussion of the ideal of one fundamental ontology.

References

  • Alexander, Joshua, Ron Mallon, and Jonathan M. Weinberg. 2010. Accentuate the Negative. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (2): 297–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atran, Scott, and Douglas L. Medin. 2008. The Native Mind and the Cultural Construction of Nature. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, Karen. 2009. Composition, Colocation and Metaontology. In Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, eds. David John Chalmers, David Manley and Ryan Wasserman, 38–75. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, Brent. 1992. Ethnobiological Classification. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, Simon. 2010. The Absolute Conception: Putnam Vs Williams. Practical Tortoise Raising: and other Philosophical Essays, Simon Blackburn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf. 1950. Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4: 20–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David. 2009. Ontological Anti-Realism. In Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, eds. David John Chalmers, David Manley and Ryan Wasserman, 77–129, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve, James. 2008. The Moon and Sixpence: A Defense of Mereological Universalism. In Contemporary debates in metaphysics, eds. Ted Sider, John Hawthorne and Dean W Zimmerman, 321–366. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp, David. 2006. The Ontology of Putnam’s Ethics without Ontology. Contemporary Pragmatism 3 (2): 39–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dale, Rick. 2008. The Possibility of a Pluralist Cognitive Science. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 20(3): 155–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel C. 2013. Kinds of Things. Bestiary of the Manifest Image. In Scientific Metaphysics, eds. Don Ross, James Ladyman, and Harold Kincaid, 96–107. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dorr, Cian, and Gideon Rosen. 2002. Composition as Fiction. In Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics, ed. Richard M Gale, 151–74. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eklund, Matti. (2013). “Carnap’s Metaontology,” Noûs, 47(2), 229–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, Arthur. 1998. The Viewpoint of No-One in Particular. In Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 7–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guarino, Nicola, Daniel Oberle, and Steffen Staab. 2009. What is an Ontology?. Handbook on ontologies, eds. Steffen Staab and Rudi Studer, 1–17, Berlin: Springer Berlin Heidelberg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, Eli. 2002. Quantifier Variance and Realism. Philosophical Issues 12 (1): 51–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, Eli. 2011. Quantifier Variance and Realism: Essays in Metaontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, Terry, and Matjaž Potrč. 2006. Abundant Truth in an Austere World. Truth and Realism: New Essays, eds. Michael Lynch & Patrick Greenough, 137–67. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, Peter. 1990. Material Beings. Cornell: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, Uriah. 2013. The Epistemological Challenge of Revisionary Metaphysics. Philosophers Imprint 13 (12): 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, David. 2015. Indigenous and Scientific Kinds. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, first published online,.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, Trenton. 2001. Objects and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mulder, Jesse M. 2012. What Generates the Realism/Anti-Realism Dichotomy. Philosophica 84: 49–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Thomas. 1989. The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pihlström, Sami. 2006. Putnam’s Conception of Ontology. Contemporary Pragmatism 3 (2): 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 1987. Truth and Convention: On Davidson’s Refutation of Conceptual Relativism. Dialectica 41 (1-2): 69–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 1988. Representation and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 2009. Ethics Without Ontology. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 2012. From Quantum Mechanics to Ethics and Back Again Reading Putnam, eds. Peter Clark and Bob Hale, 19–36. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1948. On What There Is. Review of Metaphysics 2 (5): 21—36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, Wilfrid. 1963. Philosophy and the scientific image of man. Science, perception and reality 2: 35–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tallant, Jonathan. 2014. Against Mereological Nihilism. Synthese 191 (7): 1511–1527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, Amie. 2007. Ordinary Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, Amie. 2012. Experimental Philosophy and the Methods of Ontology. The Monist 95 (2): 175–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Peter. 1979. There are no ordinary things. Synthese 41 (2): 117–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Peter. 2005. All the Power in the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, Ted. 2012. Writing the Book of the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 2011. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ludwig, D. (2015). Conceptual Relativity in Philosophy. In: A Pluralist Theory of the Mind. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-22738-2_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics