Skip to main content

Body, Time and Subject

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Biology and Subjectivity

Part of the book series: Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action ((HSNA,volume 2))

  • 449 Accesses

Abstract

Is it possible to reconcile an objective, scientific description of the body with the subjective experience of being or having a body? This chapter argues that because an objective account understands subjectivity as a function of the biological organism, it fails to explain the complex and often paradoxical relation between subjectivity and corporeity. Contemporary philosophers such as Plessner, Heidegger and Jonas have pointed out the importance of the concept of life for understanding subjectivity. Moreover, through their analysis of life, they confirm Kant’s insight into the close relationship between subjectivity and temporality. It is no mystery that many attempts to reconcile subjectivity and the body fail to capture movement and time, as they often rely on definitions of living systems for which time is always extrinsic. A different and more successful strategy is to invoke the Aristotelian concept of enérgeia, or perfect activity, to describe the distinctive character of living processes. This notion also illuminates the role of consciousness, which at face value appears to be out of time, thus posing an even harder problem. For Aristotle, consciousness depends on a vital activity: the activity of the intellect (nous). Thus this chapter integrates the discoveries of contemporary biology with key Aristotelian concepts like enérgeia and nous to develop a concept of the living body as a center of coordinated vital activities, including the generation of consciousness, presence and temporality, and to grasp their characteristic temporality as synchrony. This view inspires both an understanding of the body as more than a mere thing, and a means of reconciling the atemporality of conscious experience with the instability and exteriority of our body.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    From a phenomenological perspective, the importance of corporeality as an inherent determinant of all experience has been highlighted in a radical – and, in my view, somewhat one-sided – way, by Hermann Schmitz (2011). He goes so far in his attempt to avoid the dualism and mentalism of much of the Western tradition that the distinction we have been discussing between the interior and exterior perspectives seems to vanish.

  2. 2.

    A philosophical example of this view is the Self-Model Theory of Thomas Metzinger (2003). For a critical survey of this theory, see Murillo (2011).

  3. 3.

    “Körperliche Dinge der Anschauung, an welchen eine prinzipell divergente Außen-Innenbeziehung als zu ihrem Sein gehörig geständlich auftritt, heißen lebendig” (1981, p. 138).

  4. 4.

    “Positional liegt ein Dreifaches vor: des Lebendige ist Körper, im Körper (als Innenleben oder Seele) und außer der Körper al Blickpunkt, von dem aus es beides ist. Ein Individuum, welches positional derart dreifach charakterisiert ist, heißt Person. Er ist das Subjekt seines Erlebens, seines Aktionen, seiner Initiative. Es weiß und es will. Seine Existenz ist Wahrhaft auf Nichts gestellt” (1981, p. 365).

  5. 5.

    Fuchs calls the brain a “mediating organ” (2013).

  6. 6.

    Bruno Snell (2000, pp. 13–20) points out that in ancient Greek art and literature the body is not seen as an organic unity until the fifth century BCE. Previously the body was seen as different parts added to each other. They were melea kai gyia, that is, parts with muscle, strong, articulated and able to move. The word soma, however, that corresponds to our term “body ” was only used by Homer as meaning “corpse.” What we call “body ” is referred to in plural as a collection of members and is considered from the point of view of human activity.

  7. 7.

    “A system can be defined as a complex of interacting elements” (von Bertalanffy 1969, p. 55).

  8. 8.

    This affinity between the notion of system and mathematic s is especially evident in the cited work of von Bertalanffy (1969).

  9. 9.

    “Change is analogous to spatial variation. Change does occur in virtue of unchanging facts about temporal parts.” Sider (2001, p. 214).

  10. 10.

    “The organizational account of functions relies, then, on the theoretical assumption according to which the various temporal instances of a system, in spite of any changes which may occur, can be considered as instances of the same encompassing self-maintaining organization, to the extent that their constitutive organizational properties are causally transmitted from one instance to another instance by the maintenance of a material connection between them” (Saborido et al. 2011, p. 599).

  11. 11.

    In a similar way Scheler distinguishes between functions and actions: “First, all functions are ego-functions; they never belong to the sphere of the person. Functions are psychic; acts are non-psychic. Acts [loving, hating, judging, for example] are executed; functions happen by themselves. Functions necessarily require a lived body and an environment to which the ‘appearances’ of functions belong. But with the person and acts we do not posit a lived body ; and to the person there corresponds a world, not an environment . Acts spring from the person into time; functions are facts in phenomenal time and can be measured indirectly by coordinating their phenomenal time-relations with measurable lengths of time appearances given in functions themselves. For example, seeing, hearing, tasting, and smelling belong to functions, as do all kinds of noticing, noting and taking notice of (and not only so-called sensible attention to) vital feeling, etc. (…)” (Scheler 1973, p. 388). Concerning the different ways of experiencing the self in knowledge and action, see Murillo (2009).

  12. 12.

    “Time is nothing other than the form of inner sense, i.e., of the intuition of our self and our inner state” (Kant 1998, A 33, B 49).

  13. 13.

    In addition to following the Aristotelian text here, I will also integrate Leonardo Polo ’s proposal, which declares itself to be a continuation and further development of Aristotelian philosophy. See Polo (2003, 2006).

  14. 14.

    Medieval Aristotelianism usually translated this distinction between perfect activity and movement as inmanens and transitiva: “Action is twofold. Actions of one kind pass out to external matter [transiens], as to heat or to cut; whilst actions of the other kind remain in the agent [inmanens], as to understand, to sense and to will. The difference between them is this, that the former action is the perfection not of the agent that moves, but of the thing moved; whereas the latter action is the perfection of the agent” (Summa Theologiae, I, q. 18, a. 3 ad 1).

  15. 15.

    The notion of the cogitative sense does not appear as such in Aristotle , but is common in the later Aristotelian tradition.

  16. 16.

    The word enérgeia which I have translated in this text as “activity” is usually translated into Latin as actus.

  17. 17.

    This fact legitimates the consideration of living beings as systems and their activities as processes, provided that they are not ontologically characterized by these concepts.

References

  • Aquinas, Th. 1888–1889. Pars Prima Summae Theologiae. Opera omnia, IV–V. Rome: Ex Typographia Polyglotta S. C. de Propaganda Fide.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, Th. 1961. In Summa Contra Gentiles, Books 2–3, ed. P. Marc, C. Pera, and P. Caramello. Turin/Rome: Marietti.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1924. Metaphysics. W.D. Ross, 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Reprinted 1953 with corrections.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1983. Physics. Books III and IV, trans. with notes E. Hussey. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 2002. Nicomachean ethics. Trans. (with historical introduction) Ch. Rowe; philosophical introduction and commentary S Broadie. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behnke, E. 2004. Edmund Husserl’s contribution to phenomenology of the body in Ideas II. In Phenomenology. critical concepts in philosophy. Volume II: Phenomenology: Themes and issues, ed. D. Moran and L.E. Embree. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carman, T. 1999. The body in Husserl and Merleau-Ponty. Philosophical Topics 27(2): 205–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A.D. 2003. Interoception: The sense of the physiological condition of the body. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 13(4): 500–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, Th. 2000. Leib, Raum, Person. Entwurf einer phänomenologischen Anthropologie. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, Th. 2013. Das Gehirn – ein Beziehungsorgan: eine phenomenologische und ökologische Konzeption, 4th edn. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. 1992. Gesammelte Werke. 20, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse, (1830). Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. 1996. Being and Time. Trans. J. Stambaugh. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 1984. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy, trans. D. Carr. Evanston: Northwestern University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 1989. Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. Second Book. Studies in the phenomenology of constitution. Trans. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. 1992. Evolution und Freiheit. In Philosophische Untersuchungen und metaphysische Vermutungen. Frankfurt: Insel Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. 2001. The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1998. Critique of pure reason. Trans. A. Wood and P. Guyer. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leder, D. 1990. The absent body. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. 1964. The philosopher and his shadow. In Signs. Trans. R. McCleary. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. 2010. Oeuvres. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, Th. 2003. Being no one. The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murillo, J.I. 1999. ¿Son realmente autónomas las ciencias? In Fe y Razón. I Simposio Internacional Fe cristiana y cultura contemporánea, ed. J. Aranguren, J. Borobia, and M. Lluch. Pamplona: Eunsa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murillo, J.I. 2008. Health as a norm and principle of intelligibility. In Natural law: Historical, systematic and juridical approaches, ed. A.N. García, M. Silar, and J.M. Torralba. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholar Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murillo, J.I. 2009. ¿Comprender la libertad? Entre la biología y la metafísica. Anuario Filosófico, XLII/2: 391–418.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murillo, J.I. 2011. Apariencia y realidad del yo: una aproximación crítica a la propuesta de Thomas Metzinger. In Asalto a lo mental. Neurociencias, consciencia y libertad, ed. F. Rodríguez Valls, C. Diosdado, and J. Arana. Madrid: Biblioteca Nueva.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plessner, H. 1981. Gesammelte Schriften. IV: Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polo, L. 2003. Antropología trascendental. Tomo II: La esencia de la persona humana. Pamplona: Eunsa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polo, L. 2006. Curso de teoría del conocimiento. Tomo I. Pamplona: Eunsa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saborido, Ch, M. Mossio, and A. Moreno. 2011. Biological organization and cross-generation functions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62: 583–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. 1973. Formalism in ethics and non-formal ethics of values. A new attempt toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism. Trans. M.S. Frings and R.L. Funk. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Schelling, F.W.J. 2000. System des Transzendentalen Idealismus. Hamburg: Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitz, H., R.O. Müllan, and J. Slaby. 2011. Emotions outside the box—The new phenomenology of feeling and corporeality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10(2): 241–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. 2001. Four-dimensionalism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Snell, B. 2000. Die Entdeckung des Geistes: Studien zur Entstehung des europäischen Denkens bei den Griechen. Göttingen: Vadenhoeck und Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, R. 2008. Phenomenology of the human person. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spaemann, R., and R. Löw. 2005. Natürliche Ziele: Geschichte und Wiederentdeckung des teologischen Denkens. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bertalanffy, L. 1969. General system theory: Foundations, development, applications. New York: George Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welton, D. 1999. The body: Classic and contemporary readings. Malden: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to José Ignacio Murillo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Murillo, J.I. (2016). Body, Time and Subject. In: García-Valdecasas, M., Murillo, J., Barrett, N. (eds) Biology and Subjectivity. Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30502-8_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics