Skip to main content

Free Will, Responsibility and Moral Evil

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Human Being, the World and God

Abstract

While the previous chapter considered empathy and compassion, this chapter looks at some reasons for why empathy and compassion sometimes fail to prevail. What could be the reasons that some dismiss or even lack empathy? Furthermore, where does free will come in? Is there something like free will or is free will always relative to a specific factor? Is free will equal to being free? In my opinion having free will and being free is not entirely the same. For instance, a drug addict may have freely chosen to start taking drugs, but after some time it is the drug that chooses the addict who is no longer a free person. Take the following example. I am completely free to choose what I want to do today, I may choose to continue writing on my book or I may choose to do something entirely different. However, I am not free from my duty to submit the book in time. Then, of course, one could try to refrain from making a choice, thinking in terms of ‘what has to happen also happens’. However, that will not work, one will end up making a choice because “[w]e cannot think away our free will” (Searle 2007: 43). However, that we cannot think away our free will does not mean that we have absolute free will. In turn, this does not mean that free will is an illusion. As Searle expresses, “free will is a genuine feature of the world” (Searle 2007: 58). Therefore, it needs to have neurological correlations. The choices we make cannot be detached from our neurological set-up. This implies that human free will to do good or bad is at least partly hardwired in the brain.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    My translation from Danish.

  2. 2.

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-religion/accessed 5 February 2016.

  3. 3.

    The difference between Kant’s moral philosophy and Utilitarianism is that Kant sees the good will as an end while Utilitarianists see the good will as a means, i.e. in a derivative sense.

  4. 4.

    Kant does not believe in the doctrine that Jesus Christ took away the guilt of previous evil (vicarious atonement) but argues that we should see Christ’s actions as an example (exemplary atonement).

  5. 5.

    Perhaps this note is unnecessary but Kant did not have access to psychological or neuroscientific studies on moral behavior as we have today.

  6. 6.

    Of course, a lack or loss of empathy and an increase of violence may also be caused by drug abuse.

  7. 7.

    The amygdala which is located in the middle part of the temporal lobes is one of the oldest structures in the brain and controls and mediates virtually all high-order emotional functions. However, as argued above, one should be aware of the fact that no neural activity stands alone. Amongst other neural functions the amygdala is connected to frontal lobe activity which is maintained to be responsible for higher cognitive functions. Epileptogenic focus is the area of the cerebral cortex (the outer portion of the brain) responsible for causing epileptic seizures.

  8. 8.

    Also in the superior temporal sulcus, the anterior insular, and the areas of the premotor cortex. Both the cognitive (frontal) and affective (limbic) processes are interwoven in neural networks that participate in mediating the empathic response (high-level empathy).

  9. 9.

    fMRI studies on the perception of pain in others also showed that there is a difference in neural activity when evaluating the pain of others compared to evaluating one’s own pain.

  10. 10.

    I have already shown the importance of the amygdala, the frontal and temporal cortex and the insula for empathy to emerge. The striatum, or neostriatum or striat nucleus is a subcortical part of the forebrain and very significant for the reward system.

  11. 11.

    http://www.infoplease.com/spot/jonestown1.html accessed 15 February 2016.

  12. 12.

    We are not discussing the sect-leaders, only the members.

  13. 13.

    http://www.neh.gov/humanities/2014/marchapril/feature/the-trial-hannah-arendt accessed 21 Aug. 2014.

References

  • Aargaard, M. 2007. Berglinske, Thursday 8 November, 09:02.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adolphs, Ralph, Daniel Tranel, Hanna Damasio, and Antonio R. Damasio. 1995. Fear and the human Amygdala. Journal of Neuroscience 15: 5879–5891.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aharoni, E., W. Sinntt-Armstrong, and K.A. Keihl. 2012. Can psychopathic offenders discern moral wrongs? A neo look at the moral/conventional distinction. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 121: 484–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderberg, Thomas. 1997. Guds moral: En essä om lidandets och ondskans problem. Nora: Nya Doxa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aniskiewicz, Albert S. 1979. Autonomic component of vicarious conditioning and psychopathy. Journal of Clinical Psychology 35: 60–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 2006. Eichmann in Jerusalem. A report on the Babality of evil. New York: Penguin Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beier, Matthias. 2006. On the psychology of violent christian fundamentalism: Fighting to matter ultimately. Psychoanalytic Review 93(2): 301–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bretherton, Inge, J. Fritz, C. Zahn-Waxler, and D. Ridgeway. 1986. The acquisition and development of emotion language: A functionalist perspective. Child Development 57: 529–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, Richard. 2001. How has the world changed? The Guardian. Interview

    Google Scholar 

  • Decety, Jean. 2014. The neuroevolution of empathy and caring for others: Why it matter for morality. In New frontiers in social neuroscience, ed. Jean Decety and Yves Christen, 127–152. Heidenberg/New York/Dordrecht/London: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Decety, Jean, and Philip L. Jackson. 2007. The functional architecture of human empathy. Behavioral and Cognitive Neuroscience Reviews 3(2): 71–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fieldman, George. 2003. Evolution and evil. Perspectives on Evil and Human Wickedness 1(3): 122–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goleman, Daniel. 1997. Emotional intelligence, why it can matter more than IQ. New York: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, S.M. 2006. The end of faith. London: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1654. Treatise of ‘Liberty and Necessity’. Available on http://isites.harvard.edu/fs/docs/icb.topic1223571.files/hobbes%20on%20liberty.pdf. Assessed 8 Feb 2016.

  • Jones, Kathleen, B. 2014. The trial of Hannah Arendt. Humanities 35(2). http://www.neh.gov/humanities/2014/marchapril/feature/the-trial-hannah-arendt. Accessed 21 Aug 2014.

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1960. Religion within the limits of reason alone. New York: The Open Court Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 2014. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-religion/. Accessed 5 Feb 2016.

  • Pink, Thomas. 2004. Free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Proctor, James, D. 2005. Frans de Waal and Evan Thompson, Interviewed by James Proctor. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12(7):38–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reyes, Hermán. 2007. The worst scars are in the mind: Psychological torture. International Review 89(867): 591–616.

    Google Scholar 

  • Runehov, Anne L.C. 2010. Why evil will not go away: A philosophical analysis of the complexity of the problem of evil. In SSTh XII: Studies in science & theology, eds. Dirk Evers, Antje Jackelén and Taede A. Smedes, 325–344. Tübingen: Forum Scientiarum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 2007. Freedom & neurobiology. Reflecting on free will, language and political power. New York/Chichester: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shamay-Tsoory, Simon G., Rachel Tomer, B.D. Berger, D. Goldsher and J. Aharon-Peretz. 2005. The neural correlates of understanding the other’s distress: A positron emission tomography investigation of accurate empathy. NeuroImage 27(2);468–472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, P., E.J. Lawrence, C. Radbourne, J. Bramham, C.E. Polkey, and A.S. David. 2004. The impact of early and late damage to the human amygdala on ‘theory of mind’ reasoning. Brain 127: 1535–1548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprengelmeyer, R., A.W. Young, U. Schroeder, P.G. Grossenbacher, J. Federlein and T. Buttner. 1999. Knowing no fear. Proceedings of the Royal Society (Series B: Biology), 266:2451–2456.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Evan. 2001. Empathy and consciousness. Journal of Conscious Studies 8(5–7): 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiser, James L. 1983. Political philosophy: A history of the search for order. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, Nick. 2006. Explaining human cruelty. Behavior and Brain Sciences 29: 245–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Runehov, A.L.C. (2016). Free Will, Responsibility and Moral Evil. In: The Human Being, the World and God. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-44392-8_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics