Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
User-friendly Legal Science
  • 338 Accesses

Abstract

Normal legal science has not been able to prevail in the competition for scientific hegemony. Moreover, normal legal science is less practice ready than it could be. User-friendly Legal Science is a legal discipline designed to help. Its unique point of view is how users can use legal tools and practices to reach their objectives in different contexts. While normal legal science focuses on legal norms, User-friendly Legal Science primarily studies behaviour.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Kant I (1783), § 1.

  2. 2.

    Kant I (1793), p. 61.

  3. 3.

    Bacon F (1620), book I, aphorism 81: “Meta autem scientiarum vera et legitima non alia est, quam ut dotetur vita humana noviis inventis et copiis.”

  4. 4.

    von Kirchmann J (1848), p. 23: “As science takes the arbitrary as its object, it becomes arbitrary itself; three corrective words from the legislator, and entire libraries turn into maculature.”

  5. 5.

    Hart HLA (1961/ 2012), pp. 88–90.

  6. 6.

    von Savigny FC (1814).

  7. 7.

    Ehrlich E (1913), pp. 382–383.

  8. 8.

    Heck P (1914); Stigler GJ (1971).

  9. 9.

    For legal rhetoric, see White JB (2002), p. 1399; Perelman C (1977); Gast W (2015). For the effect of psychological types, see Novak M (2014).

  10. 10.

    von Kirchmann J (1848); von Jhering R (1858); Larenz K (1966), p. 11; Ulen TS (2002).

  11. 11.

    History was defined as the frame of reference even in von Jhering R (1858), pp. 75–76: “Denn die Geschichte selber ist, wie Hegel gesagt hat, das Weltgericht; die Sünden der Väter strafen sich an den Kindern, und wer in der Geschichte suchen will, was gut und böse, der wird es erkennen können an dem Segen, der auch hier auf der guten, und dem Fluch, der auf der bösen Tat ruht.” Hegel GWF (1820/1821), § 343: “Die Geschichte des Geistes ist seine Tat, denn er ist nur, was er tut …”

  12. 12.

    See already Holmes OW (1897).

  13. 13.

    Kuhn TS (1970).

  14. 14.

    For the problematic relationship between legal theory and practice, see, for example, Posner RA (2002), p. 1316; Jestaedt M (2006).

  15. 15.

    Goodhart CAE (1997).

  16. 16.

    See Grundmann S, Micklitz HW, Renner M (eds) (2015); van Gestel R, Micklitz HW, Rubin EL (eds) (2016).

  17. 17.

    Holmes OW (1897), p. 469; Posner RA (2002), p. 1317; LoPucki LM (2016), pp. 506 and 538.

  18. 18.

    Sieber U (2010), p. 171.

  19. 19.

    Maslow AH (1966), p. 15: “I suppose it is tempting, if the only tool you have is a hammer, to treat everything as if it were a nail.” See also Hayek FA (1944); Glendon MA (1991); Epstein RA (1992); Teubner G (2012). For an alternative to mandatory law, see, for example, Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2008).

  20. 20.

    See Posner RA (2002), pp. 1315 and 1323.

  21. 21.

    Mäntysaari P (2013).

  22. 22.

    See, for example, Iggers GG (1988) on the paradigm of historical science. For the need to choose new reference points, see Latour B (2013) pp. 29–30.

  23. 23.

    White JB (2002), p. 1397: “You learn the law in order to use it – in order to achieve a set of objectives, to establish and maintain a set of relations, to move yourself and others in a direction you wish to go, even to discover that direction.” For examples of legal “framing devices” and “referencing devices”, see Malloy RP (2004), pp. 6–8.

  24. 24.

    Wittgenstein L (1953), § 1 and § 43.

  25. 25.

    For sociology, see Weber M (1922). For other examples of the use of an interpretive approach in law, see Malloy RP (2004), pp. 56–57 and Grundmann S, Micklitz HW, Renner M (eds) (2015), p. 3.

  26. 26.

    Simon HA (1967), pp. 14–15; van Aken JE (2004).

  27. 27.

    For the pattern model of explanation, see Kaplan A (1964).

  28. 28.

    In qualitative research, it is customary to use grounded theory. See Glaser BG, Strauss AL (1967), p. 18.

  29. 29.

    See, for example, Glaser BG, Strauss AL (1967), p. 3.

  30. 30.

    Kant I (1793), p. 61: “… a middle term is required between theory and practice …” Edwards HT (1992–1993), p. 34: “While the schools are moving toward pure theory, the (law) firms are moving toward pure commerce, and the middle ground – ethical practice – has been deserted by both.”

  31. 31.

    Lewin K (1945), p. 129.

  32. 32.

    van Aken JE (2004), p. 220.

  33. 33.

    For economics, see Friedman M (1953), p. 15.

  34. 34.

    Hydén H (2011), p. 122: “To put it in a nutshell, how does one get from ‘is’ to ‘ought’? … Within the system under investigation, there is an in-built, taken for granted rationality that decides what is right and what is wrong.” According to what is known as Hume’s guillotine, it is not obvious how one can coherently move from descriptive statements to prescriptive ones. Hume D (1739), book III, part I, section I.

  35. 35.

    Banakar R (2006), p. 78: “I argue, therefore, that legal scholars can break new grounds once they turn outwards, for only if they step outside law, they can view their undertaking in different, and perhaps new, lights.”

  36. 36.

    See also Hart HLA (1961/ 2012), p. 40 on the “puzzled man”; White JB (2002), p. 1397; Banakar R, Travers M (2005b), p. 134.

  37. 37.

    For example, legal concepts can be regarded as “ideal-types” that can be made subject to an empirical investigation. Weber M (1949), p. 43 (a translation of Weber M 1913). For legal history, see Lobban M (2012), paragraph 29: “One of the tasks of the legal historian speaking to a wider historical audience is to remind them that the language which lawyers and legal officials use, and the operation of their institutions play a crucial part in the governance of society and in structuring private relations.” For the traditional view, however, see Ross A (1958), p. 34.

  38. 38.

    von Wright GH (1971), p. 96. See, for example, Kusch N (2003), p. 350.

  39. 39.

    Ross A (1958), pp. 331 and 328; Bourdieu P (1975), p. 19; Simon HA (1967), p. 15. Basedow J (2014): “What is often denounced as a wave of neo-liberalism that has flooded the world has in reality ensued from a mix of economic, political and comparative legal investigations.”

  40. 40.

    For innovation and the constructive approach, see Kasanen E, Lukka K, Siitonen A (1993), p. 246.

  41. 41.

    Compare Ross A (1958), p. 334 on legal politics as a science: “… the principle of purity of science requires, that every political directive shall name the objectives and attitudes which are accepted as hypothetical premises guiding the theoretical researches and the practical conclusions …” Critically on Ross’ science Dalberg-Larsen J (2005), p. 47.

  42. 42.

    Grundmann S, Micklitz HW, Renner M (eds) (2015), p. 4: “Von der Übersetzungsleistung der Rechtstheorie kann die Rechtsdogmatik profitieren: Sie kann sich mit Hilfe der Rechtstheorie ein genaueres Bild der gesellschaftlichen Kontexte Machen, in denen Rechtsregeln wirken.”

  43. 43.

    Dagan H (2011), p. xviii: “For legal realists, the profound and inescapable reason for doctrinal indeterminacy is the availability of multiple and potentially applicable doctrinal sources.” Berman HJ (1983), p. 11: “The conventional concept of law as a body of rules derived from statutes and court decisions … is wholly inadequate to support a study of a transnational legal culture.”

  44. 44.

    For management accounting theory, see Kasanen E, Lukka K, Siitonen A (1993), p. 252: “Truly functioning constructions have great commercial value.”

  45. 45.

    Dewey J (1938), Chapter 1; Saurama E, Julkunen I (2012), p. 61: “What Dewey wanted to do was to restore the value of the needs of practical life in the field of knowledge formation; although practice is uncertain, chaotic and volatile, it is nevertheless the reality within which people have to solve the problems they face.” See also Simon HA (1967), p. 15 (on the organisational problem of professional schools); van Aken JE (2004), p. 219 (management research and business schools).

  46. 46.

    See, for example, Banakar R, Travers M (2005a), p. 19.

  47. 47.

    For interpretive management accounting research, see Elharidy AM, Nicholson B, Scapens RW (2008), p. 142. For legal history, see Duss V (2012), p. 989.

  48. 48.

    See also Kaplan A (1964), § 1, p. 3.

  49. 49.

    Hart HLA (1961/2012), pp. 88–90.

  50. 50.

    Alf Ross divided the science of law into, first, legal dogmatics or jurisprudence that studies legal norms and, second, the sociology of law that studies law in action. See Ross A (1958), § 4; Dalberg-Larsen J (2005), p. 41.

  51. 51.

    Bourdieu P (1975), pp. 38–39.

  52. 52.

    Kuhn TS (1970), Chapter 6.

References

  • Bacon F (1620) Novum Organum. Apud Joannem Billium, Typographum Regium, Londini

    Google Scholar 

  • Banakar R (2006) How can sociology and jurisprudence learn from each other? A reply to Mauro Zamboni. Retfærd 29(2):75–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Banakar R, Travers M (2005a) Law, sociology and method. In: Banakar R, Travers M (eds) Theory and method in socio-legal research. Hart Publishing, Oxford and Portland Oregon, pp 1–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Banakar R, Travers M (2005b) Studying legal texts. In: Banakar R, Travers M (eds) Theory and method in socio-legal research. Hart Publishing, Oxford and Portland Oregon, pp 133–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Basedow J (2014) Comparative law and its clients. Am J Comp Law 62(4):821–857

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berman HJ (1983) Law and revolution: the formation of the Western legal tradition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu P (1975) The specificity of the scientific field and the social conditions of the progress of reason. Soc Sci Inf 14(6):19–47. doi:10.1177/053901847501400602

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dagan H (2011) Property: values and institutions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dalberg-Larsen J (2005) Alf Ross and the sociology of law. Scandinavian Stud Law 48:39–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey J (1938) Experience and education. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Duss V (2012) Chronik. Arbeitskreis “Augen der Rechtsgeschichte”. Fünftes Symposium zur Methode der Rechtsgeschichte. Einsiedeln 20.-22. January 2011. Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung für Rechtsgeschichte. Germanistische Abteilung 129(1):986–990. doi:10.7767/zrgga.2012.129.1.986

  • Edwards HT (1992–1993) The growing disjunction between legal education and the legal profession. Mich Law Rev 34:34–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehrlich E (1913) Grundlegung der Soziologie des Rechts. Duncker & Humblot, München and Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Elharidy AM, Nicholson B, Scapens RW (2008) Using grounded theory in interpretive management accounting research. Qual Res Accounting Manag 5(2):139–155. doi:10.1108/11766090810888935

  • Epstein RA (1992) Book review. Rights and ‘Rights Talk’. Harv Law Rev 105:1106–1123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1953) The methodology of positive economics. In: Friedman M (ed) Essays in positive economics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 3–43

    Google Scholar 

  • Gast W (2015) Juristische Rhetorik. 5., überarbeitete und erweiterte Auflage. C.F. Müller Verlag, Heidelberg

    Google Scholar 

  • Glaser BG, Strauss AL (1967) The discovery of grounded theory: strategies for qualitative research. Aldine de Gruyter, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Glendon MA (1991) Rights and ‘Rights Talk’: the impoverishment of political discourse. The Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodhart CAE (1997) Economics and the law: too much one-way traffic? Mod Law Rev 60(1):1–2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grundmann S, Micklitz HW, Renner M (eds) (2015) Privatrechtstheorie. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (2012) The concept of law, 3rd ed. With an introduction by Leslie Green. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1944) The road to serfdom. George Routledge & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Heck P (1914) Gesetzesauslegung und Interessenjurisprudenz. Archiv für die civilistische Pracis 112:1–318

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel GWF (1820/1821) Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts; oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse. Nicolaische Buchhandlung, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes OW (1897) The path of the law. Harv Law Rev 10:457–490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1739) A treatise of human nature. John Noon, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hydén H (2011) Looking at the world through the lenses of norms. Nine reasons for norms: a plea for norm science. In: Papendorf K, Machura S, Andenaes K (eds) Understanding law in society. Developments in socio-legal studies. LIT Verlag, Berlin, pp 120–159

    Google Scholar 

  • Iggers GG (1988) The crisis of the Rankean paradigm in the nineteenth century. Syracuse Scholar (1979–1991) 9(1), Article 7

    Google Scholar 

  • Jestaedt M (2006) Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein … Vom Nutzen der Rechtstheorie für die Rechtspraxis. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1783) Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können. Johann Friedrich Hartknoch, Riga

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1793) Über den Gemeinspruch: Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein, taugt aber nicht für die Praxis. Berlinische Monatsschrift 22:201–284. English translation: On the common saying: ‘this may be true in theory but it does not apply in practice’. In: Reiss H (ed) (1991) Kant: Political writings. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 61–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan A (1964) The conduct of inquiry: methodology for behavioral science. Chandler Publishing Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kasanen E, Lukka K, Siitonen A (1993) The constructive approach in management accounting research. J Manag Accounting Res 5:243–264

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, Second edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch M (2003) Explanation and understanding: the debate over von Wright’s philosophy of action revisited. In: Haaparanta L, Niiniluoto I (eds) Analytic philosophy in Finland. Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 80. Rodopi, Amsterdam New York, pp 327–356

    Google Scholar 

  • Larenz K (1966) Über die Unentbehrlichkeit der Jurisprudenz als Wissenschaft. Vortrag gehalten vor der Berliner Juristischen Gesellschaft am 20. April 1966. Schriftenreihe der Juristischen Gesellschaft zu Berlin 26

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour B (2013) An inquiry into modes of existence: an anthropology of the moderns. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewin K (1945) The research center for group dynamics at Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Sociometry 8(2):126–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lobban M (2012) The varieties of legal history. Clio@Thémis 5:1–29

    Google Scholar 

  • LoPucki LM (2016) Dawn of the discipline-based law faculty. J Leg Educ 65:506–542

    Google Scholar 

  • Malloy RP (2004) Law in a market context: an introduction to market concepts in legal reasoning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mäntysaari P (2013) Was sollte man tun? Ein Plädoyer für anwenderfreundliche Rechtswissenschaft. Rechtstheorie 44(2):189–207. doi:10.3790/rth.44.2.189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maslow AH (1966) The psychology of science: a reconnaissance. Harper & Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Novak M (2014) A typological reading of prevailing legal theories. Ratio Juris 27(2):218–235. doi:10.1111/raju.12042

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perelman C (1977) L'empire rhétorique. Rhétorique et argumentation. J. Vrin, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner RA (2002) Legal scholarship today. Harv Law Rev 115(5):1314–1326

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross A (1958) On law and justice. Stevens & Sons Limited, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Saurama E, Julkunen I (2012) Approaching practice research in theory and practice. Soc Work Soc Sci Rev 15(2):57–75. doi:10.1921/095352211X636502

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieber U (2010) Rechtliche Ordnung in einer globalen Welt. Die Entwicklung zu einem fragmentierten System von nationalen, internationalen und privaten Normen. Rechtstheorie 41(2):151–198. doi:10.3790/rth.41.2.151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1967) The business school: a problem in organizational design. J Manag Stud 4(1):1–16. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6486.1967.tb00569.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stigler GJ (1971) The theory of economic regulation. Bell J Econ Manag Sci 2(1):3–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teubner G (2012) Verfassungsfragmente. Gesellschaftlicher Konstitutionalismus in der Globalisierung. Suhrkamp, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2008) Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Ulen TS (2002) A Nobel Prize in legal science: theory, empirical work, and the scientific method in the study of law. Univ Illinois Law Rev 4:875–920

    Google Scholar 

  • van Aken JE (2004) Management research based on the paradigm of the design sciences: the quest for field-tested and grounded technological rules. J Manag Stud 41(2):219–246

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gestel R, Micklitz HW, Rubin EL (eds) (2016) Rethinking legal scholarship: a transatlantic dialogue. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • von Jhering R (1858) Geist des römischen Rechts auf den verschiedenen Stufen seiner Entwicklung. Druck und Verlag von Breitkopf und Härtel, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • von Kirchmann J (1848) Die Werthlosigkeit der Jurisprudenz als Wissenschaft. Verlage von Julius Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • von Savigny FC (1814) Vom Beruf unsrer Zeit für Gesetzgebung und Rechtswissenschaft. Mohr und Zimmer, Heidelberg

    Google Scholar 

  • von Wright GH (1971) Explanation and understanding. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (1922) Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft – Grundriß der verstehenden Soziologie. J.C.B Mohr (Paul Siebeck), Tübingen

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (1949) The methodology of the social sciences. The Free Press, Glencoe

    Google Scholar 

  • White JB (2002) Legal knowledge. Harv Law Rev 115(5):1396–1431

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1953) Philosophische Untersuchungen. In: Anscombe GEM, von Wright GH, Rhees R (eds) Werkausgabe, Band 1. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt (1984), pp 224–485

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mäntysaari, P. (2017). Introduction. In: User-friendly Legal Science. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-53492-3_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-53492-3_1

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-53491-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-53492-3

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics