Skip to main content

Toward a Positive Taxonomy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Real Fourdimensionalism

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 130))

  • 203 Accesses

Abstract

The fourth chapter discusses various challenges that have been brought forth against different version of 4-dimensionalism. I explicate a positive taxonomy of those questions the sensible 4-dimensionalist needs to answer in order to provide an adequate theory of persistence. In particular, I discuss: the no change objection, the objection from “a crazy metaphysics”, modal concerns, and the argument from motion in homogeneous masses.

Philosophy is to be studied, not for the sake of any definite answers to its questions since no definite answers can, as a rule, be known to be true, but rather for the sake of the questions themselves; because these questions enlarge our conception of what is possible, ….

(Russell 1959, Chapter 15)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a brief summary of the different theories, I refer to Zimmerman (2005b, 401–405).

  2. 2.

    This idea can be traced back to Thomas Aquinas (1976, 5–8) and Aristotle.

  3. 3.

    Only in a figurative sense can this be called a ‘dispute.’

  4. 4.

    I will not be able to discuss the motivations behind Parmenides’s and Heraclitus’s ontologies of persistence, but will only present briefly their central theses.

  5. 5.

    These arguments are only tentative. They shall motivate the problem of change, not give a complete formal and substantial account. I will address this question, when discussing the recent analytic debate.

  6. 6.

    Please note that I am going to employ a loose definition of the concept of change in the following discussion and arguments. A detailed one follows in the subsequent section

  7. 7.

    The notion of real change is used intuitively. Real change involves something staying the same while changing in a relevant way. I will discuss the notion of change in more detail below.

  8. 8.

    A concise summary of this argument has been provided by Peter Geach in his paper on Some Problems about Time (1972, 309).

  9. 9.

    Within the following table, x and y denote concrete particulars or temporal parts. C might be any characteristic of a concrete particular. The remaining symbols are used according to their normal definitions.

  10. 10.

    Perhaps the most famous example of this issue is the case of the black spheres that are discussed in the controversy between bundle-theorists and proponents of bare-substrata

  11. 11.

    Logically speaking this is to be treated as an exclusive ‘or’ (XOR).

  12. 12.

    I will exclude here any position defending 4-dimensionalism and non-material souls or similar.

  13. 13.

    I.e. Doctrine of Temporal Parts or 4-dimensionalism.

  14. 14.

    Again, we need to use motion and change equivalently.

  15. 15.

    There are different formulations of this puzzle. In a recent paper, Robin LePoidevin (2011, 462–463) defends a formulation similar to that given here, from the perspective of time, consciousness, causation, and free will. LePoidevin’s formulation relies on the following assumption. Causally efficacious acts of free will is necessarily tied to consciousness, which is temporally extended. However, the concept of the present is necessarily instantaneous (the A-theory). There seems to be a basic inconsistency between the basic relation of times and consciousness.

    I think that this puzzle mirrors the puzzle addressed here: Just like the A-theory has been shown to conflict with human freedom (LePoidevin 2011, 464), I have argued that both 3-dimensionalism as well as 4-dimensionalism conflict with change.

  16. 16.

    For a more detailed discussion of properties at times and temporal properties, I refer to Pablo Rychter (see e.g. 2008, 168–171) or Ariel Meirav (see e.g. 2009, 135).

  17. 17.

    Although, it needs to be noted that there are some philosophers denying that there is genuine problem of change – see for example Pablo Rychter (2009, 7–22).

  18. 18.

    The quotation has been modified to fit the example used in this re-formulation: ‘H’ has been replaced by ‘C’, ‘alpha’ by ‘l old ’ and ‘beta’ by ‘l new ’.

  19. 19.

    This is in fact a problem that is applicable to almost any theory of persistence. Considering the question of the persistence of human persons; John Hawthorne argues along these lines, see for example (2006, 186).

  20. 20.

    A similar definition has been quoted by Matti Eklund – originally the idea stems from Elizabeth Barnes: “Sentence S is ontically vague iff were all …content precisified, there would be an admissible precisifaction …such that …the sentence would still be non epistemically indeterminate in a way that is sorites susceptible.” (Eklund 2011, 154). I decided to formulate my definition of sharp temporal boundaries in a more straight-forward way, but I think that – basically – both definitions are analogous.

  21. 21.

    I am going to provide a short, partially-formalized version of my respective claims at the end of each bullet point. Here are the relevant logical termini used in the argument:

    The predicate E(x,t) denotes that some entity, x, exists at some temporal location, t. Nota bene: I am aware that, since Kant, ‘to exist’ has not been commonly treated as an ordinary predicate. Nevertheless, for the sake of the clarity of my argument, I am going to allow ‘existential-predication’. This seems to be rather unproblematic, because the predicate E is restricted to ‘spatio-temporal existence’ and is, thus, not equivalent to unrestricted existence claims. For a detailed analysis of restricted and unrestricted existence-predicates, see Priest (2005, 105–115).

    The term \(\exists\) C1 …C n : E(z) denotes that there are conditions C 1 …C n explaining the relevant matter of fact z. It is important to note that E(z) is in fact a meta-predicate. It provides information about whether some relevant term can be explained coherently within the context of a certain theory.

  22. 22.

    Another prominent argument against vague existence has been proposed by Ted Sider in various papers: Sider (2001, 120) and Sider (2003, 135–146). However, Sider’s argument has been proposed in a synchronic fashion. Thus, it seemed necessary to apply the basic ideas of his argument to persistence-problems.

  23. 23.

    For an explanation of the symbols used in this formalization, please refer to the second step of my argument about the incompatibility of realistic vagueness and 4-dimensionalism (see Argument 4.3 – 1).

  24. 24.

    Number in […] are insertions by the author.

  25. 25.

    Again, passages in italics are my accentuations

  26. 26.

    Translation by Kemp-Smith (1929).

  27. 27.

    Recent research on the possibility of such approaches has been made by Elizabeth Barnes and J. Robert Williams. I refer to Barnes (2011a, 103–148), Barnes (2011b, 173–183) and Woodward (2011, 187).

  28. 28.

    Translated by me.

  29. 29.

    Galen Strawson’s discussion of Nagarjuna’s thought can be said to be one example illustrating this idea: Strawson (2009a, 303, 313) and Nagarjuna (2010, chapter 9).

  30. 30.

    I borrow this phrase from van Inwagen (1990b, 253).

  31. 31.

    The basic idea here is that sums of temporal parts constitute new individuals – i.e. temporally extended wholes – as discussed in the Lesniewskian approach to mereological summing. A detailed introduction can be found in Simons’s Parts (1987, pt. 1 ch. 2).

    NB: As of now, I will be using Simons’s terminology for mereological questions. Nevertheless, \(\mathbb{C}\) still denotes temporally extended wholes and C denotes temporal parts of temporally extended wholes.

  32. 32.

    NB: This argument is in fact a reconstruction of van Inwagen’s original ideas. I tried to make van Inwagen’s point as strong as possible. Nevertheless, I refrain from the assertion that this argument is a perfect mirror of van Inwagen’s original idea.

  33. 33.

    It is apparently impossible to obtain the early volumes of The Pacific Philosophical Quarterly in Germany. This is why I will be citing a re-print of this paper from Ontology, Identity, and Modality: Essays in Metaphysics.

  34. 34.

    For a concise example of such an argument, see Kearns (2005, 3–8).

  35. 35.

    A classical argument for this assertion can be found in Kripke (1971, 135/72). Nevertheless, as Kripke’s paper shows even this claim has not gone undisputed.

  36. 36.

    For another, similar interpretation of this matter of fact, see Hawley (2001, 191–194). Nevertheless, Hawley’s count of the respective approaches differs from mine.

  37. 37.

    Credit should be given to Jonathan Jacob’s Causal Powers (2007, 165–183) that contributed heavily to the ideas sketched here.

  38. 38.

    In fact, we have seen that the concept of natural vs. negative possibility gets extremely complex very fast. For a short systematic introduction into truthmaking and possibility within the context of a similar version of actualism, I refer to Robert Adams’s Actualism and Thisness (1981, 20–38).

  39. 39.

    In fact, this is a move that has been popular among Aristotelian philosophers.

  40. 40.

    Some philosophers have wondered whether Aristotelian modest realism is consistent with a 4-dimensional ontology of persistence. I agree that this is indeed an interesting question. Recall our previous discussion: 4-dimensionalists believe that concrete particulars persist by having temporal parts. I already argued that 4-dimensionalists are not forced to assert the priority of the B-series (see Taxonomy of 4D – Step 1.3). And I defended the idea that 4-dimensionalists should be either eternalists or growing blockers (see Taxonomy of 4D – Step 2.4). Neither of these criteria seem to conflict with Aristotelian modest realism. This is why I think that 4-dimensionalsts can safely adopt the Aristotelian framework of modality. Nevertheless, I do not think that 4-dimensionalists should adopt the Aristotelian theory of concrete particulars. I think that the alleged inconsistency of Aristotelian modal theory and 4-dimensionalism stems from the fact that people think that Aristotelian modal theory entails the theory of ousiai. That is not the case.

  41. 41.

    The following discussion stems from my summary of the following articles. Anybody interested into RDA should take a look at those papers: Zimmerman (1998, 265–288), Lewis (1999b, 209–212), Zimmerman (1999, 213–215), Scala (2002, 393–397), Zimmerman (2002, 398–405) and most importantly Butterfield (2006, 1–45)

  42. 42.

    Any similarity to living philosophers is purely incidental.

References

  • Adams, Robert. 1981. Actualism and thisness. Synthese 49(1): 3–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, Thomas. 1976. Opera Omnia. Iussi Leonis XIII P.M. Edita, vol. Tomus XLIII. Roma: Editori di San Tommasso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1937 ff. The works of Aristotle, Ross, w.d. ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. Met.Z. Metaphysics. Books Z and H. Translated by David Bostock. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, Elizabeth. 2011a. A theory of metaphysical indeterminacy. In Oxford studies in metaphysics, vol. 6, ed. Dean Zimmerman, 103–148. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, Elizabeth. 2011b. Response to Eklund. In Oxford studies in metaphysics, vol. 6, ed. Dean Zimmerman, 173–182. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benovsky, Jiri. 2008. There are vague objects (in any sense in which there are ordinary objects). Studia Philosophica Estonica 1(3): 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, Max. 1952. The identity of indiscernibles. Mind 61(242): 153–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brand, Cordula. 2010. Personale Identität oder menschliche Persistenz? Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, Andrew. 1988. Conditions of identity. A study in identity and survival. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, Jeremy. 2006. The rotating discs argument defeated. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57(1): 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, Richard. 1975. Scattered objects. In Analysis and metaphysics: Essays in honor of Roderick M. Chisholm. Philosophical studies, ed. Keith Lehrer, 153–171. Berlin: springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David. 2009. Ontological anti-realism. In Metametaphysics – New essays on the foundations of ontology, ed. David Chalmers, 77–129. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobreros, Pablo. 2011. Supervaluationism and Fara’s argument concerning higher-order vagueness. In Vagueness and language use. Palgrave studies in pragmatics, language, and cognition, ed. Paul Egré, 207–221. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diels, Hermann, and Walther Kranz, ed. 1903. Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Hildesheim: Weidman’sche Verlagsbuchhandlung.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eklund, Matti. 2011. Being metaphysically unsettled. Barnes and Williams on metaphysical indeterminacy and vagueness. In Oxford studies in metaphysics, vol. 6, ed. Dean Zimmerman, 149–172. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Geach, Peter F. 1972. Some problems about time. In Logic matters, ed. Peter F. Geach, 302–317. Hoboken: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, George. 1977. Persons and time. Southern Journal of Philosophy 15(3): 309–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Han, Xiaoqiang. 2009. The criterion or criteria of change. Metaphysica. International Journal for Metaphysics and Ontology 11(2): 149–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, Tobias. 2007. The problem(s) of change revisited. Dialectica 61(2): 265–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, Katherine. 2001. How things persist. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, Katherine. 2015b. Temporal parts. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy Winter 2015. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/temporal-parts/

  • Hawthorne, John. 1992. Leibnizian essentialism, transworld identity, and counterparts. History of Philosophy Quarterly 9(4): 425–444.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, John. 2005. Vagueness and the mind of god. Philosophical Studies 122(1): 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, John. 2006. Epistemicism and semantic plasticity. In Metaphysical essays, ed. John Hawthorne, 185–211. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, John. 2008. The many minds account of vagueness. Philosophical Studies 138(3): 435–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, Mark. 1984. Temporal parts of fourdimensional objects. Philosophical Studies 46(3): 323–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, Mark. 1990. The ontology of physical objects. Fourdimensional hunks of matter. Cambridge studies in philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller, Mark. 1992. Things change. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52(3): 695–704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, Mark. 1993. Varieties of four dimensionalism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71(1): 47–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, Mark, and William Carter. 1989. Metaphysical boundaries: a question of independence. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 67(3): 263–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofweber, Thomas. 2009. The meta-problem of change. Nous 43(2): 286–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, Hud. 2000. Universalism, four dimensionalism and vagueness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60(3): 547–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, Hud. 2001. A materialist metaphysics of the human person. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, Hud. 2005. The metaphysics of hyperspace. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, Jonathan. 2007. Causal powers. A neo-aristotelian metaphysic. PhD dissertation, Indiana University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1903. Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1. Auflage), Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik, die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können, Grundlegung der Metaphysik der Sitten, Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft. Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften, vol. IV. Berlin: Königlich Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1904. Kritik der reinen Vernunft, zweite Auflage, 1787. Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften, vol. III. Berlin: Königlich Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearns, Stephen. 2005. Against the doctrine of arbitrary undetached parts. Presented at the 9th Annual Oxford Philosophy Graduate Conference.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, Saul. 1971. Identity and necessity. In Identify and individuation, ed. Milton Munitz, 135–164. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • LePoidevin, Robin. 2011. The temporal prison. Analysis 71(3): 462–463.

    Google Scholar 

  • LePoidevin, Robin. 2015. The experience and perception of time. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy Summer 2015. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/time-experience/

  • Lewis, David. 1986a. On the plurality of worlds. Hoboken: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David. 1986b. Counterfactuals. Original 1972, Corrected 1986, Reissued 2001. Hoboken: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David. 1999a. Many, but almost one. In Essays in metaphysics and epistemology, ed. David Lewis, 164–182. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David. 1999b. Zimmerman and the spinning sphere. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77(2): 209–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lombard, Lawrence Brian. 1994. The doctrine of temporal parts and the no-change-objection. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54(2): 365–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, Jonathan. 2006. The 3D/4D controversy: A storm in a teacup. Nous 40(3): 570–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magidor, Ofra. 2016. Endurantism vs. Perdurantism? A debate reconsidered. Nous 50(3): 509–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, Charles Burton, and John Heil. 1999. The ontological turn. Midwest studies in philosophy 23(1): 34–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McTaggart, John. 1908. The unreality of time. Mind 17(68): 457–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McTaggart, John. 1921/27. The nature of existence, vol. i+ii. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meirav, Ariel. 2009. Properties that four-dimensional objects cannot have. Metaphysica. International Journal for Metaphysics and Ontology 11(2): 135–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, Hugh. 1998. Real Time II. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagarjuna. 2010. Die Lehre vom mittleren Weg. Chinesisch-deutsch. Aus dem chinesischen Text des Kumarajiva übersetzt und mit einem Kommentar herausgegeben von Lutz Geldsetzer. Hamburg: Meiner Verlagsbuchhandlung.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, David. 1993. The metaphysics of identity over time. London: St. Martin’s Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, David. 2004. Temporal parts and the possibility of change. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69(3): 686–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, Alvin. 1974. The nature of necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, Graham. 2005. Towards non-being. The logic and metaphysics of intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, Frank. 1929/1978. Theories. In Foundations: Essay in philosophy, logic, mathematics, and economics, 101–125. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rea, Michael. 2003. Four-dimensionalism. In Oxford handbook of metaphysics. Oxford handbooks, ed. Michael Loux and Dean Zimmerman, 246–280. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1903. The principles of mathematics, 1996 Norton paperback-edition; reprint of the second edition from 1938 ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1959. The problems of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rychter, Pablo. 2008. Perdurance, endurance, and ‘Having a Property Atemporally’. Metaphysica. International Journal for Metaphysics and Ontology 10(2): 159–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rychter, Pablo. 2009. There is no puzzle about change. Dialectica 63(1): 7–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scala, Mark. 2002. Homogeneous simples. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64(2): 393–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, Sidney. 1988. On what there are. Philosophical Topics 16(1): 201–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, Ted. 2001. Four dimensionalism. An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, Ted. 2003. Against vague existence. Philosophical Studies 114(1–2): 135–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons, Peter. 1987. Parts. A study in ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, Peter. 2000. Continuants and occurrents. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74(1): 59–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, Roy. 1996. The metaphysics of words. Philosophical Studies 81(2/3): 193–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, Roy. 2016. Vagueness. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy Spring 2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/vagueness/

  • Strawson, Galen. 2009a. Selves. An essay in revisionary metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, Peter Frederick. 1959. Individuals. An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Teller, Paul. 2002. The rotating disk argument and Humean supervenience: Cutting the gordian knot. Analysis 62(3): 205–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1983. Parthood and identity across time. The Journal of Philosophy 80(4): 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, Peter. 1981. The doctrine of arbitrary undetached parts. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 62(1): 123–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, Peter. 1990b. Four-dimensional objects. Nous 24(2): 245–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, Peter. 2001. The doctrine of arbitrary undetached parts. In Ontology, identity, and modality: Essays in metaphysics, ed. Peter van Inwagen, 75–94. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varzi, Achille. 2005. Change, temporal parts, and the argument from vagueness. Dialectica 59(4): 485–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, Brian. 2015. The problem of the many. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy Winter 2015. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/problem-of-many/

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1922/2003. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. New York, NYC: Barnes and Nobles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, Richard. 2011. Metaphysical indeterminacy and vague existence. In Oxford studies in metaphysics, vol. 6, ed. Dean Zimmerman, 183–195. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Yagisawa, Takashi. 2014. Possible objects. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy Fall 2014. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/possible-objects/

  • Zimmerman, Dean. 1995. Theories of masses and problems of constitution. The Philosophical Review 104(1): 53–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Dean. 1997. Immanent causation. Nous Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives 11. Mind, Causation and World 11(1): 433–471.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Dean. 1998. Temporal parts and supervenient causation: The incompatibility of two Humean doctrines. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76(2): 265–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Dean. 1999. One really big liquid sphere: Reply to Lewis. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77(2): 213–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Dean. 2002. Scala and the spinning spheres. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64(2): 398–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Dean. 2005b. The A-theory of time, the B-theory of time and ‘Taking Tense Seriously’. Dialectica 59(4): 401–457.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Dean. 2011. Presentism and the space-time manifold. In Oxford handbook of philosophy of time. Oxford handbooks, ed. Craig Callender, 163–245. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Jaskolla, L. (2017). Toward a Positive Taxonomy. In: Real Fourdimensionalism. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 130. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-65927-5_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics