Skip to main content

The Experiments of Willem Jacob ’s Gravesande: A Validation of Leibnizian Dynamics Against Newton?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
What Does it Mean to be an Empiricist?

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 331))

Abstract

In 1720, Willem Jacob ’s Gravesande wrote Physicis elementa mathematica, experimentis confirmata. Sive introductio ad philosophiam Newtonianam (An Introduction to Sir Isaac Newton’s Philosophy; or, Mathematical Elements of Natural Philosophy, Confirmed by Experiments). Although he was undoubtedly one of the most important popularizers of Newtonian physics, experimental methodology and epistemology in the 1720s, his empirical claim somehow backfired: in applying tenets of Newtonian methodology, he was ultimately led to validate the Leibnizian principle of the conservation of living forces, contrary to the Newtonians. This conclusion invited a great deal of anger, particularly from Samuel Clarke who, in a volume of the Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society from 1729, accused ’s Gravesande of having written the book with the aim of “darkening Newton’s philosophy”. In a reply, which ’s Gravesande published as a supplement to his Essay upon a New Theory of the Collision of Bodies, he developed a hybrid methodology that relied upon both experimentation and reason. In my paper, I shall thoroughly analyse this interesting combination.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Iltis (1973), 344.

  2. 2.

    As is well known, in 1720, ’s Gravesande published the first volume of his major treatise Physices elementa mathematica experimentis confirmata, sive introductio ad philosophiam Newtonianam (the second was published in 1721). In 1723, he decided to publish a compendium called Philosophiae newtonianae institutiones, in which he added a chapter on the measurement of living forces (’s Gravesande 1720b–21, 1723).

  3. 3.

    Israel (2001), 524: “Willem Jacob ’s Gravesande, the Leiden professor who did more than anyone else to engineer the triumph of English philosophy and science in the Dutch mainstream Enlightenment in the 1720s, was essentially a Newtonian who turned to Locke only in the 1730s and, even then, never gave much prominence to his ideas.”

  4. 4.

    Feingold (2004), 72: “His lectures and his publications [...] rendered Newton’s abstruse mathematical physics into visual and dramatical experimental demonstrations”.

  5. 5.

    Clarke (1728), especially 382.

  6. 6.

    Clarke commonly read the discrepancies between what he himself considered to be Newtonian orthodoxy, as ignorance or misunderstandings of Newtonian concepts; concepts not “rightly” used by particular authors.

  7. 7.

    Steffen Ducheyne very convincingly shows how the omission of the 4th regulae philosophandi in ’s Gravesande’s Physices Elementa is not accidental, but a conscious decision to develop “a major epistemological and methodological difference” from Newton (see Ducheyne 2014b, 100). It is also important to observe, as Ducheyne did, the difference of meanings between Newton and ’s Gravesande.

  8. 8.

    See Ducheyne 2014a, b.

  9. 9.

    Ducheyne (2012).

  10. 10.

    Cassirer (1951), 61.

  11. 11.

    “Je ne suis pas tout a fait pour le Criterium de des Cartes. Parce que dans la geometrie mesme on s’imagine souvent de comprendre tres clairement des choses qui sont fausses. Il y reste donc tousjours a scavoir si l’on a compris clairement et distinctement, ce qui est. assez douteux dans de longues demonstrations. Et de la naissent les paralogismes. Je serais donc plus pour les divers degrez de vraisemblance, laquelle dans certaines rencontres est si grande que d’estre quelque fois comme 100,000,000,000 et plus contre un, que le vray ou le faux d’une proposition, et qu’en de certaines choses cela va comme a l’infini.” (Christian Huygens to Burcher de Volder, September 1691, in: Huygens (1888–1950), vol. X, 739, letter no. 2701a).

  12. 12.

    Especially regarding his interpretation of the absence of miraculous acts in the Cartesian world.

  13. 13.

    It seems to be a paradox because of all the quarrels triggered between Leibniz and Newton.

  14. 14.

    Gerhard Wiesenfeldt argued in his book Leerer Raum in Minervas Haus: Experimentalle Naturlehre an Der Universitat Leiden, 1675–1715 that this kind of “Theatrum physicum” did mark the end of Cartesianism (Wiesenfeldt 2002, 90). On the contrary for some commentators, it means the beginning of a Cartesian empiricism (see, for example, van Bunge 2013 and Nyden 2013). My point is slightly distinct: I argue that there were many different experimental traditions before the introduction of Newton’s philosophy (without presupposing the life or the death of Cartesianism), precisely because it seems to me that this kind of categorization darkens the historical interpretation of the thought.

  15. 15.

    See Lunsingh Scheurleer et al. (1975).

  16. 16.

    See Brunet (1926), 40; see also de Volder’s eulogy by Jean Leclerc: “Il fut cette même année en Angleterre, où il demeura quelques semaines, pour y voir les habiles gens de ce païs-là. Je ne sai s’il fut content de son voyage, car je ne me souviens pas de lui en avoir rien ouï dire. Il avoit un peu apris d’Anglois et il en savoit assez, pour entendre les livres écrits en cette Langue; sur tout ceux qui traitent de matieres, qui concernoient ses Etudes; c’est à dire la Philosophie et les Mathematiques.

    Ce fut apparemment la Société Royale d’Angleterre, toute occupée à rechercher la Vérité, par la voie des Experiences, et peutêtre l’exemple de l’illustre Mr Boyle, qui en étoit comme l’ame et qui faisoit une grande dépense en son particulier pour cela, qui firent naître à Mr. de Volder la pensée de proposer à Mrs. les Curateurs de l’Academie de faire quelque dépense pour la même chose. Il le leur persuada et ces Mrs. acheterent un endroit près de l’Academie, qu’ils firent disposer en forme de théatre, afin que les Etudians pussent voir commodément les Experiences de Physique et de Méchanique, que Mr. de Volder feroit devant eux” (Leclerc 1709, 362–363).

  17. 17.

    See Chareix (2006) and Nyden (2014), especially 207–208.

  18. 18.

    See ’s Gravesande (1736).

  19. 19.

    See ’s Gravesande (1736). In other texts, specifically dedicated to physics, for example “Essai d’une nouvelle théorie du choc des corps” (’s Gravesande (1722), this interaction is more inconspicuous.

  20. 20.

    Gori (1972), 181.

  21. 21.

    Steffen Ducheyne has exhaustively documented the history of interpretation of this moral certainty (Ducheyne 2014a). See also Gori (1972), 218; Pater (1995); and more recently: Schuurman (2004), especially 143.

  22. 22.

    Ducheyne extensively analyzes this conception of analogy “proven” by God: “analogy is guaranteed by the fact that God governs the universe by invariable laws”.

  23. 23.

    At this point, it is very interesting to note how ’s Gravesande plays with the relationship between certainty and probability established by John Locke (Locke 1706, chap. XVI, sec. 6).

  24. 24.

    In this perspective, it seems important to place ’s Gravesande’s approach into the general perspective defined by Ian Hacking and Paolo Rossi, as ably summarized by Barbara J. Shapiro. The main point is the link between empiricism and probability: “Ian Hacking’s study of the origins of mathematical probability were linked to empiricism, and particularly to medicine and astrology, which made diagnoses, prognoses and predictions on the basis of observable signs. For Hacking, signs play a particularly important part in the transformation from probability in the ‘low sciences’ to mathematics. Because his primary concern is mathematics rather than philosophy or natural sciences, and his focus is on the Continent rather than England, Hacking tends to slight the role of the Royal Society. Nevertheless, both Hacking, by emphasizing astrology and medicine, and Paolo Rossi, by emphasizing technology, have made important contributions to our understanding of how experience and probability of the ‘low sciences’ made inroads into conceptions of scientific philosophy. They help to show us that natural science not only was freeing itself from the unattainable goals of scientific demonstration but was helping to shape a new mathematics more suited to scientific inquiry.” (Shapiro 1983, 38).

  25. 25.

    In the Acta Eruditorum, Mars 1686, 132.

  26. 26.

    “Il y a donc une grande différence entre la force motrice et la quantité de mouvement, à tel point que l’une ne peut être estimée à partir de l’autre [...]. Il apparaît de là que la force doit être estimée à partir de l’effet qu’elle peut produire, par exemple, la hauteur à laquelle elle peut élever un corps pesant d’une grandeur et d’une espèce déterminée.” (Leibniz 1860, 118).

  27. 27.

    Duchesneau (1994).

  28. 28.

    Iltis (1971).

  29. 29.

    Brown (1984).

  30. 30.

    Nyden (2014), 218.

  31. 31.

    Pierre Costabel in his paper “’s Gravesande et les forces vives ou des vicissitudes d’une expérience soi-disant cruciale” was the first to show that ’s Gravesande had really performed experiments, and secondly that what he did was not really a crucial experiment (see Costabel 1964).

  32. 32.

    “elle ne mène pas à des règles différentes de celles qui sont connues et que l’expérience a confirmées, mais on trouvera ici ces règles démontrées d’une manière différente de celles qu’elles ont été jusqu’à présent, et on verra comment d’un Principe contraire à l’expérience, les Philosophes sont parvenus à ces règles, par un raisonnement dans lequel ils ont négligé de faire attention à tout ce qui devait être considéré, sans quoi il était impossible de parvenir à la vérité par le chemin qu’ils avaient pris.” (’s Gravesande 1722, 2–3).

  33. 33.

    Ducheyne (2014a), 37.

  34. 34.

    Clarke (1728), 382.

  35. 35.

    Ibid., 385.

  36. 36.

    Ibid.

  37. 37.

    ’s Gravesande (1722), 3.

  38. 38.

    Clarke (1728), 381–382.

  39. 39.

    As argued by Steffen Ducheyne: “[eighteenth century scholars] are gradually freeing Enlightenment science from its ‘Newtonian straight jacket’” (Ducheyne 2014a, 31).

Bibliography

Other Primary Literature

  • Clarke, Samuel. 1728. A Letter from the Rev. Dr. Samuel Clarke to Mr. Benjamin Hoadly, F.R.S. Occasion’d by the Present Controversy among Mathematicians, concerning the Proportion of Velocity and Force in Bodies in Motion. Philosophical Transactions 35 (1727): 381–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • ’s Gravesande, Willem Jacob. 1720–1721. Physices elementa mathematica experimentis confirmata, sive introductio ad philosophiam Newtonianam. Leiden: Pieter van der Aa.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1722. Essai d’une nouvelle théorie du choc des corps fondée sur l’experience. The Hague: T. Johnson.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1723. Philosophiae newtonianae institutiones. Leiden: Pieter van der Aa.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1736. Introductio ad Philosophiam, Metaphysicam et Logicam continens. ed. Leyden: J. and H. Verbeek (2nd ed. 1737, French transl. 1737).

    Google Scholar 

  • Huygens, Christiaan. 1888–1950. Œuvres complètes. The Hague: Nijhoff /Société hollandaise des sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leclerc, Jean. 1709. Eloge de feu Mr. de Volder, Professeur de Philosophie et aux Mathematiques, dans l’Academie de Leide. Bibliothèque choisie XVIII: 346–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1860. Brevis demonstratio, In: Ibid.: Leibnizens gesammelte Werke, ed. by Georg Heinrich Pertz, Dritte, C.I. Gerhardt, vol. 6, 117–119. Halle/Folge: H.W. Schmidt/Mathematik.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1706. An essay concerning human understanding. 5th ed. London: Churchill.

    Google Scholar 

Secondary Literature

  • Brown, Gregory. 1984. ‘Quod ostendendum susceperamus?’ What did Leibniz Undertake to Show in Brevis Demonstratio? Leibniz’ Dynamica, Studia Leibnitiana, Sonderheft 13: 122–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunet, Pierre. 1926. Les Physiciens hollandais et la méthode expérimentale en France au XVIII e siècle. Paris: Albert Blanchard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, Wiep van. 2013. Dutch Cartesian Empiricism and the Advent of Newtonianism. In Cartesian Empiricisms, ed. Mihnea Dobre and Tammy Nyden, 89–104. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, Ernst. 1951. The philosophy of the enlightenment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chareix, Fabien. 2006. La philosophie naturelle de Christiaan Huygens. Paris: Vrin. (Mathesis).

    Google Scholar 

  • Costabel, Pierre. 1964. ’s Gravesande et les forces vives ou des vicissitudes d’une expérience soi-disant cruciale. In Mélanges Alexandre Koyré, vol. I: “L’aventure de la science”, 117–134. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duchesneau, François. 1994. La dynamique de Leibniz. Paris: Librairie philosophique J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne, Steffen. 2012. The main business of natural philosophy: Isaac Newton’s natural-philosophical methodology. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014a. ’s Gravesande’s appropriation of Newton’s natural philosophy, part I: Epistemological and theological issues. Centaurus 56 (1): 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014b. ’s Gravesande’s appropriation of Newton’s natural philosophy, Part II: Methodological issues. Centaurus 56 (2): 97–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feingold, Mordechai. 2004. The Newtonian moment. Isaac Newton and the making of modern culture. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gori, Giambattista. 1972. La fondazione dell’esperienza in ‘s Gravesande. Florence: La Nuova Italia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iltis, Carolyn. 1971. Leibniz and the Vis Viva Controversy. Isis 62: 21–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1973. The Leibnizian-Newtonian Debates: Natural philosophy and social psychology. The British Journal for the History of Science 6 (4): 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Israel, Jonathan. 2001. Radical enlightenment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lunsingh Scheurleer, Theodoor Herman, et al. 1975. Leiden University in the seventeenth century: An exchange of learning. Brill: Leyden.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nyden, Tammy. 2013. “De Volder’s Cartesian physics and experimental pedagogy”, in: Dobre, Mihnea and Nyden, Tammy (eds.) (2013): Cartesian empiricisms. Dordrecht: Springer, 227-249.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Living force at Leiden. De Volder, ’s Gravesande and the reception of newtonianism. In Newton and empiricism, ed. Zvi Biener and Eric Schliesser, 207–222. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pater, Kees de. 1995. ’s Gravesande on moral evidence. In Frans Hemsterhuis (1721–1790): Quellen, Philosophie und Rezeption, ed. Marcel F. Fresco, Loek Geeraedts, and Klaus Hammacher, 221–242. Münster/Hamburg, Lit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuurman, Paul. 2004. Ideas, mental faculties and method. The logic of ideas of descartes and Locke and its reception in the Dutch Republic, 16301750. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Barbara. 1983. Probability and certainty in seventeenth-century England. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiesenfeldt, Gerhard. 2002. Leerer Raum in Minervas Haus. Experimentelle Naturlehre an der Universität Leiden, 16751715. Amsterdam: Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anne-Lise Rey .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Rey, AL. (2018). The Experiments of Willem Jacob ’s Gravesande: A Validation of Leibnizian Dynamics Against Newton?. In: Bodenmann, S., Rey, AL. (eds) What Does it Mean to be an Empiricist?. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 331. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-69860-1_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics