Skip to main content

The Dialogical Roots of Equality: Dialogues for Immanent Reasoning

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Immanent Reasoning or Equality in Action

Part of the book series: Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning ((LARI,volume 18))

  • 244 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter we will spell out all the relevant rules of dialogues for immanent reasoning, that is, the dialogical framework incorporating features of Constructive Type Theory—a dialogical framework making the players’ reasons for asserting a proposition explicit. The rules can be divided, just as in the standard framework, into rules determining local meaning and rules determining global meaning. These include:

  1. 1.

    Concerning local meaning (Sect. 7.1):

    1. (a)

      formation rules (p. 105);

    2. (b)

      rules for the synthesis of local reasons (p. 108); and

    3. (c)

      rules for the analysis of local reasons (p. 109).

  2. 2.

    Concerning global meaning, we have the following (structural) rules (Sect. 7.2):

    1. (a)

      rules for the resolution of instructions (p. 112);

    2. (b)

      rules for the substitution of instructions (p. 113);

    3. (c)

      equality rules determined by the application of the Socratic rules (p. 113); and

    4. (d)

      rules for the transmission of equality (p. 115).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This rule is an expression at the level of plays of the rule for the substitution of variables in a hypothetical judgement . See (Martin-Löf, 1984, pp. 9–11).

  2. 2.

    As a matter of fact, increasing her repetition rank would allow O to play the two alternatives for move 3 within a single play. But increasing the Opponent’s rank usually yields redundancies (Clerbout, 2014a, 2014b) making things harder to understand for readers not familiar with the dialogical approach; hence our choice to divide the example into different simple plays.

  3. 3.

    See (Sundholm, 1986, pp. 501–503) and (Ranta, 1994, pp. 77–99) .

  4. 4.

    This yields an asymmetry in the structural rules . For a discussion on the consequences of this feature and how it is closely linked to the symmetry of the particle rules, see Sect. 4.3 and Sect. 11.3.

  5. 5.

    Note that P is allowed to make an elementary statement only as a thesis (Socratic rule); he will be able to respond to the challenge on an elementary statement only if O has provided the required local reason in her initial concessions.

  6. 6.

    See below, Sect. 7.3, for an illustration.

  7. 7.

    See for instance \( {\mathcal{P}}_1 \)in Sect. 7.6.10 for an illustration.

  8. 8.

    The symmetry used here is not the same notion as the symmetry of Sect. 4.3.

  9. 9.

    This assumption is analogous to the assumption in Sect. 5.2 that O chooses a new constant when she can. The reason is the same: it is the best possible choice for O. Indeed, here also P is restricted by the Socratic rule , so he needs to rely on O’s choices in order to copy a move. In such a context , the only way to (try to) block the use of this kind of equality is to always choose, whenever possible, a new local reason.

  10. 10.

    The reason is similar to the previous one: it is better for O to force P to makes his choice as soon as possible.

  11. 11.

    See (Clerbout, 2014a, 2014c): if there is a move by which the Opponent can force her victory, then nothing prevents her from playing it as soon as she has a chance to. Whether this move is a challenge or a defence, the repetition rank 1 is enough to allow her to play it in accordance with SR1i.

  12. 12.

    Chapter 9 will focus on proving that dialogues for immanent reasoning is an admissible logical framework; it will therefore be rather technical and will address problems that mainly concern logicians, though we will here take care to outline the main philosophical aspects involved.

  13. 13.

    Among these variations can be counted cooperative games, non-monotony, the possibility of player errors or of limited knowledge or ressources, to cite but a few options the play level offers, making the dialogical framework very well adapted for history and philosophy of logic.

  14. 14.

    The table which follows is in fact the dialogical analogue to the introduction rules in CTT: dialogically speaking, these rules display the duties required by P’s assertions —we will come back to this issue in Sect. 9.1.

  15. 15.

    See (Martin-Löf, 1984, pp. 66–67).

References

  • Cardascia, P. (2016). Dialogique des matrices. Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clerbout, N. (2014a). First-order dialogical games and tableaux. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43(4), 785–801.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clerbout, N. (2014b). Étude sur quelques sémantiques dialogiques: Concepts fondamentaux et éléments de métathéorie. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clerbout, N. (2014c). Finiteness of plays and the dialogical problem of decidability. IfCoLog Journal of Logics and their Applications, 1(1), 115–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clerbout, N., & Rahman, S. (2015). Linking game-theoretical approaches with constructive Type theory: Dialogical strategies as CTT-demonstrations. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Felscher, W. (1985). Dialogues as a foundation for intuitionistic logic. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic, 3 (pp. 341–372). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keiff, L. (2007). Le Pluralisme dialogique: Approches dynamiques de l’argumentation formelle. PhD thesis, Lille.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin-Löf, P. (1984). Intuitionistic type theory. Notes by Giovanni Sambin of a Series of Lectures given in Padua, June 1980. Naples, Italy: Bibliopolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahman, S., & Tulenheimo, T. (2009). From games to dialogues and back: Towards a general frame for validity. In O. Majer, A. Pietarinen, & T. Tulenheimo (Eds.), Games: Unifying logic, language and philosophy (pp. 153–208). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rahman, S., Clerbout, N., & Keiff, L. (2009). On dialogues and natural deduction. In G. Primiero & S. Rahman (Eds.), Acts of knowledge: History, philosophy and logic: Essays dedicated to Göran Sundholm (pp. 301–336). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ranta, A. (1994). Type-theoretical grammar. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sundholm, G. (1986). Proof Theory and Meaning. In In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic, 3 (pp. 471–506). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Rahman, S., McConaughey, Z., Klev, A., Clerbout, N. (2018). The Dialogical Roots of Equality: Dialogues for Immanent Reasoning. In: Immanent Reasoning or Equality in Action. Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning, vol 18. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-91149-6_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics