Skip to main content

Prospects of Objective Knowledge

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Interdisciplinary Anthropology
  • 796 Accesses

Abstract

When looking at modern epistemology, one might come to the conclusion that the prospects for a solid realism are not so good. Two main sources for this common assessment can be identified: (1) First of all, Logical Positivism has initiated a new phase in the recent history of philosophy that was first and foremost characterized by a commitment to science. It has become evident, however, in the development of this tradition that the early hopes for a new foundation of a strong epistemic realism were soon disappointed: Tendencies toward internalism, constructivism, pragmatism, antirealism, or even cultural relativism were established. The most important steps in this development will be analyzed in the first part of the chapter: The working hypothesis in the short sketch of the historical development of epistemology is that a certain ultimately Cartesian and antievolutionary dualism plays the decisive role in the formative period of modern realism. It is this same dualism that leads from realism to more skeptical positions. By taking this Cartesian opposition for granted, modern realism again turns from empiricism to internalism or linguistic idealism. The main argument against realism will be examined and rejected: the defense of a coherent realism is only then impossible if one accepts the dualism of mind and world in the first place. But in this case most arguments against realism become a powerless tautology.

(2) Secondly, it will be argued that this implicit dualistic terminology plays also a decisive role in the interpretation of the results of the modern science of cognition. Many modern approaches to cognition begin with the claim that cognition is essentially a biological phenomenon. These views are therefore at first glance intrinsically antidualistic. But also in this domain one can trace back a shift from more realistic to more constructivist or relativistic paradigms. It will be shown that it is not surprising that the “biologization of reason” has led to two radically different interpretations: a realistic one and a more constructivistic one. It will be argued that also in these approaches the dualistic and eventually antievolutionary opposition is in fact ultimately decisive for the general philosophical and epistemological conclusions. The main point, however, is that any Evolutionary Epistemology simply cannot answer the basic problems concerning objectivity in knowledge. A positive solution is a vicious circle, the negative solution entails a self-contradiction. If one follows this line of thought then it becomes evident that only one of the interpretations can be a research paradigm that is both fruitful and does not undermine itself.

(3) The last part of the chapter following Millikan (1984, 2004), Thompson (2007), Lorenz (1973), Goodson (2003), Proust (1999) and Noë (2004), therefore focuses on a very short sketch of how the combination of a philosophical realism and an evolutionary conception of the phenomenon of cognition could be spelled out in such a way that one does not fall into the traps of either dualism or self-contradiction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a detailed analysis of the connection of the modern scientific world view and the main tenets of Logical Positivism, see Spahn (2007, 23ff.). For a critique of the main tenets of both scientistic and anti-scientistic epistemologies, see 48ff.

  2. 2.

    See Dummett (1963), a paper that started the debate about “antirealism”.

  3. 3.

    See Spahn and Tewes (2011) for an overview of the impact that the dualism between mind and world has in the philosophical debate about the theory of evolution. Naturalism it seems faces two main challenges: the qualia-problem and the problem that ethics cannot easily be naturalized.

  4. 4.

    Nagel (1986, esp. Chaps. V and VI) motivates his defense of a new realism with the correct observation that within the recent philosophy a tendency toward idealism and internalism prevails: “There is a significant strain of idealism in contemporary philosophy, according to which what there is and how things are cannot go beyond what we could in principle think about” (Nagel 1986, 9).

  5. 5.

    This insight is actually almost a tautology, but we will have to deal with its bewitching consequences later more in detail.

  6. 6.

    Think for example on the criticism of a strong adaptationism and the modern emphasis of internal constraints for any evolutionary and cognitive achievement.

  7. 7.

    Also the basic tenets of the reconciliation of realism and idealism follow some basic, eventually Hegelian, insights. For the debate on modern realism and skepticism in comparison to Hegel’s answer to skepticism, see Spahn (2011).

  8. 8.

    One might be surprised that Lorenz’ book is included. Indeed, it is “pretty old” since empirical sciences have made a lot of progress. But the conceptual order and clarity of this book is still unsurpassed.

  9. 9.

    For a more detailed account, see Spahn (2007, 16–31).

  10. 10.

    See also the very early critical essay (Rorty 1972, 3–18).

  11. 11.

    On the other hand, Putnam, of course, wants at the same time to refute the idea that we are just brains in a vat (Putnam 1981). Just how to combine the tenets of internalism and externalism remains the crucial task.

  12. 12.

    See also Spahn (2010) for a critical analysis of the debate between Nagel and Davidson.

  13. 13.

    This point is elaborated in Rorty (1979, 89) against Putnam and Davidson: “No phenomenal terms can describe the phenomenon–noumenon relation, and we have no other terms”.

  14. 14.

    This point is already at the core of the debate between Hegel and Kant about the Ding an sich, see Spahn (2004), and in relation to Nagel, see Spahn (2010), a new version of this argument can be found in Hösle (1998, 1–40).

  15. 15.

    For a more detailed analysis of the idealist trap, see Spahn (2010).

  16. 16.

    One crucial point is the distinction between the aspect of an “independent existence” of the world and the idea that it is “transcendent to knowledge in its structure”. Searle clearly sees the difficulties in using the dualistic metaphors of “inside” and “outside” for the relation of mind and world: (Searle 1983, 37). For the senses, but not for language and thinking, he therefore likes to use the word “presentation” instead of “representation” (Searle 1983, 44).

  17. 17.

    Searle avoids the ontological questions concerning representation (Searle 1983, 11). Millikan (1984) tries to sketch a naturalistic answer based on biological categories.

  18. 18.

    See Spahn (2010).

  19. 19.

    A very impressing sketch of such a “transcendental semantics” can be found in Braßel (2005).

  20. 20.

    This idea also seems to be the driving force behind Hegel’s early discussion of ancient and new skepticism; see Spahn (2011).

  21. 21.

    See also Maturana’s famous definition that life is cognition in Maturana (1980[1970]).

  22. 22.

    Thompson following Varela speaks of “sense-making” (Thompson 2007, 147). Thompson in his thoughtful “philosophy of the organism” also refers to Kant’s ideas that get expanded in Hegel’s philosophy of biology; also Hegel sees the connection of the structure of organisms and the process of “sense-making” (Spahn 2007, 194; Brandom 2004).

  23. 23.

    Also Millikan exploits biological concepts to build her theory of Intentionality (Millikan 1984, 17–50).

  24. 24.

    This point is also made by Hösle (1988).

  25. 25.

    The practical relevance of perception and cognition is therefore emphasized in the “enactive approach” to cognition; see for example: Thompson (2007, 1–87), Noë (2004).

  26. 26.

    One presupposes the objectivity of science (i.e., a product of thought) in order to argue in favor of a trust in thinking; see Hösle (1988).

  27. 27.

    http://web.mit.edu/persci/people/adelson/checkershadow_illusion.html.

  28. 28.

    Vollmer (1990) in his defense of a hypothetical realism also opposes this contravalent view and argues that there are reasons why for example we see more clearly within a certain light spectra (Vollmer 1990, 118f.)

  29. 29.

    This point that any skeptical interpretation of science relies on our cognitive ability is made against the “grand illusion” claims in modern theories of perception by Ludwig (2006).

  30. 30.

    See also Ruth Millikan’s (2004, 158f) emphasis on the ability to misrepresent things which is crucial for any real capacity for having representations.

  31. 31.

    The classic critique against behaviorism can, of course, be found in the profound analysis of Merleau-Ponty (1942), which is also extensively discussed in Thompson (2007, esp. 73–81).

  32. 32.

    Donald (2001) emphasizes among other aspects the role that language plays to get hold of the content of memory to have an even more free and flexible way to deal with things you have learned.

References

  • Brandom RB (2004) Selbstbewußtsein und Selbst-Konstitution. Die Struktur von Wünschen und Anerkennung. In: Halbig C, Quante M, Siep L (eds) Hegels Erben. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt/M, pp 46–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Braßel B (2005) Das Programm der idealen Logik. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1931) Die physikalische Sprache als Universalsprache der Wissenschaft. Erkenntnis 2:432–465

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1950) Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Rev Int Philos 4:20–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1961 [1928]) Der logische Aufbau der Welt: Scheinprobleme in der Philosophie. 2. Aufl. F. Meiner, Hamburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1973–1974) On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. In: Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association, vol 47, pp 5–20, reprinted in Davidson 2006, pp 196–208

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (2006) The essential Davidson. Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Donald M (2001) A mind so rare: the evolution of human consciousness. W.W. Norton, New York, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett M (1963) Realism, reprinted in: Truth and other Enigmas, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1978, pp 145–165

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodson F (2003) The evolution and function of cognition. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Mahwah, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Hösle V (1988) Tragweite und Grenzen der evolutionären Erkenntnistheorie. Z Allg Wissenschaftstheor 19:348–377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hösle V (1998) Objective idealism, ethics, and politics. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, IN

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas H (1966) The phenomenon of life: toward a philosophical biology. Harper & Row, New York, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz K (1941) Kants Lehre von Apriorischen im Lichte gegenwärtiger Biologie. In: Blätter für Deutsche Philosophie 15, S. 94–125

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz K (1973) Die Rückseite des Spiegels. Piper, München

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig K (2006) Is the aim of perception to provide accurate representations? In: Robert JS (ed) Contemporary debates in cognitive science. Blackwell, Malden, MA, pp 259–274

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana H (1980[1970]) Biology of cognition. In: Maturana HR, Varela FJ (eds) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana H (2003) Autopoiesis, structural coupling and cognition: a history of these and other notions in the biology of cognition. Cybern Hum Knowing 9(3–3):5–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1980[1970]) (eds) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. Dordrecht: D. Reidel publishing company

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana H, Varela FJ (1992) The tree of knowledge: the biological roots of human understanding. Shambhala/Random House, Boston, MA/New York, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1996) Mind and world: with a new introduction. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1942) La structure du comportement. Presses universitaires de France, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (1984) Language, thought and other biological categories: new foundations for realism. MIT, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (2004) The varieties of meaning. MIT, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel T (1986) The view from nowhere. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë A (2004) Action in perception. MIT, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1972) Objective knowledge: an evolutionary approach. The Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1984) Evolutionary epistemology. In: Pollard JW (ed) Evolutionary theory: paths into the future. Wiley, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Proust J (1999) Mind, space and objectivity in non-human animals. Erkenntnis 51(1):41–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam Hilary (1981) Reason, truth, and history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine W (1948) On what there is. Rev Metaphys 2(5):21–38

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine W (1960) Word and object. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine W (1968a [1958]) Speaking of objects. In: Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association, vol 31, pp 5–22, reprinted in Quine W (1969) Ontological relativity: and other essays. Columbia University Press, New York, NY, pp 1–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine W (1969a) Ontological relativity: and other essays. Columbia University Press, New York, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine W (1969b) Ontological relativity. J Philos 65(7):185–212, reprinted in Quine W (1969) Ontological relativity: and other essays. Columbia University Press, New York, NY, pp 26–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine W (1981) Theories and things. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty R (1972) The world well lost. J Philos 69(19):649–665

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty R (1979) Transcendental arguments, self-reference, and pragmatism. In: Bieri P, Horstmann R-P, Krüger L (eds) Transcendental arguments and science. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 77–103

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty R (1991) Objectivity, relativism, and truth. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle John (1983) Intentionality, an essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1995) The construction of social reality. The Free Press, New York, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars W (1956) Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In: Feigl H, Scriven M (eds) Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol 1. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN, pp 253–329

    Google Scholar 

  • Spahn C (2004) Was können wir (nicht) wissen? Vernunftkritik und metaphysischer Optimismus bei Hegel, Kant und in der Gegenwart. In: Ingensiep HW, Baranzke H, Eusterschulte A (Hg) Kant-Reader, Königshausen und Neumann, Würzburg, pp 34–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Spahn C (2007) Lebendiger Begriff, begriffenes Leben: Zur Grundlegung der Philosophie des Organischen bei G.W.F. Hegel. Königshausen und Neumann, Würzburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Spahn C (2010) Ein anderes Argument für den Idealisms? Nagel’s Ausweichen vor der Idealismusfalle. In: Geier F et al Perspektiven philosophischer Forschung, forthcoming

    Google Scholar 

  • Spahn C (2011) Alte, neue und ganz neue Skepsis? Hegels Begründung der Philosophie. In: Ficara E (ed) Die Begründung der Philosophie im deutschen Idealismus. Königshausen und Neumann, Würzburg (in press)

    Google Scholar 

  • Spahn C, Tewes C (2011) Naturalismus oder Integrativer Monismus? Zur Verhältnisbestimmung von Natur und Geist. In: Köchy K, Kolmer P (eds) Gott und Natur. Philosophische Positionen zum aktuellen Streit um die Evolutionstheorie. Karl Alber Verlag, Freiburg/München, pp 141–185

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson E (2007) Mind in life: biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (1999) The cultural origins of human cognition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooby J, Cosmides L (1992) The psychological foundations of culture. In: Barkow JH, Cosmides L, Tooby J (eds) The adapted mind: evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. Oxford University Press, New York, NY, pp 19–136

    Google Scholar 

  • Vollmer G (1990) Evolutionðre Erkenntnistheorie: angeborene Erkenntnisstrukturen im Kontext von Biologie, Psychologie, Linguistik, Philosophie und Wissenschaftstheorie. Stuttgart, Hirzel

    Google Scholar 

  • Wandschneider D (1999) Das Problem der Emergenz von Psychischem – im Anschluß an Hegels Theorie der Empfindung. In: Hösle V, Koslowski P, Schenk R (eds) Jahrbuch für Philosophie des Forschungsinstituts für Philosophie Hannover. Band 10, pp 69–95

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

I like to thank Christian Tewes, Annett Wienmeister, and André Wunder (University of Jena) for many fruitful and inspiring discussions. I like to thank Duane Lacey (United Arab Emirates University) for correcting my English.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Spahn .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Spahn, C. (2011). Prospects of Objective Knowledge. In: Welsch, W., Singer, W., Wunder, A. (eds) Interdisciplinary Anthropology. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-11668-1_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics