Skip to main content

Cosmology and the End of Weberian Science

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Scientific Knowledge and the Transgression of Boundaries

Abstract

The 2011 Nobel Prize in physics was awarded to two teams which, working independently, confirmed the striking fact that the expansion of the universe is accelerating. For many cosmologists, this prize marked another major point in the chain of successful results cosmology obtained in its relatively short history of being an experimental science. In fact, modern cosmology prides itself for becoming a “precision science ,” breaking sharply with its “speculative” past. I analyze this experimental turn in cosmology and examine different forms of interdisciplinary transgressions that this epistemic shift is built on. I propose that these transgressions that cosmology engenders in the process of establishing its scientific legitimacy attests to the fact that a crucial aspect of the way scientific knowledge is usually characterized is being challenged today. This characterization, which found, as I argue, one of its best conceptualizations in Weber ’s classic Wissenschaft als Beruf , is summarized in his famous “disenchantment ” thesis proposing that there exists a sharp boundary between the questions under the jurisdiction of science and the questions of “meaning” (such as theology), which science refuses to answer. I argue that, as the current practice of cosmology confronts this boundary, the assumptions pertinent to the social and epistemic contexts within which scientific knowledge comes into existence will also be put into question, which is what we witness in the case of modern cosmology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There is one important question that needs to be clarified for the purposes of this paper, concerning the relationship between boundary transgressions and interdisciplinarity. For one can ask whether each interdisciplinary formation corresponds to a boundary transgression, or, how a boundary transgression is different from a cooperation between two disciplines. To answer this question, we need to clarify what we mean by a “transgression”: When does a discipline transgress its boundary? Although it is beyond the scope of this paper to provide a general treatment, I propose that in any interdisciplinary formation there is an irreducible element of transgression for the following reason: When a given discipline is employed to address questions and problems that previously were classified as belonging to another one, it will need to adjust those questions to its own language and “picture of reality”, in order to be able to deal with them (here, one good example could be the situation in molecular genetics and macroscopic biology ). I suggest that it is appropriate to understand this form of disciplinary adjustment as a transgression. To be sure, I do not claim that this is the only form of transgression possible. But to the extent that it exists in all interdisciplinary constructions, this criterion justifies my treatment of them as boundary transgressions.

  2. 2.

    I chose Weber ’s text as the background for my discussion since I believe that it provides a very succinct statement of a view on science that still prevails to this day. Although I cannot propose an argument here, to the extent that Popper ’s views on the tentative character of scientific knowledge constitute one of the major threads within mainstream philosophy of science , I contend that Weber ’s lecture can be seen as a source text for what has since followed. Specifically, as we see in the quote below, it is in the idea that to be superseded scientifically is not simply our fate but our goal that I see the seeds of what will later become the central thesis of Popper ’s philosophy of science . For the classic statement of Popper ’s philosophy, see Popper (2002). A recent influential reappraisal of Popperian ideas can be found in Mayo (1996).

  3. 3.

    The original phrase is: “der Sinn der Arbeit der Wissenchaft” (Weber 2011, p. 15).

  4. 4.

    This point becomes clear when we examine how Weber contrasts art with science. He writes that when, say, a technical development occurs in art, this does not mean that the art produced as a result of this development is “superior” or “higher” to early eras, whereas in science, he thinks this is exactly the case. See Weber (2004, p. 11).

  5. 5.

    The sentence in German reads: “Und damit kommen wir zu dem Sinnproblem der Wissenschaft“ (Weber 2011, p. 15).

  6. 6.

    One should note that in this passage Weber ’s aim is to question the “point” of scientific activity and not to claim that it is “irrational”. The German original reads: “Denn das versteht sich ja doch nicht so von selbst, daß etwas, das einem solchen Gesetz unterstellt ist, Sinn und Verstand in sich selbst hat” (Weber 2011, p. 15).

  7. 7.

    Compare these observations of Weber with what we find in some of the modern cosmologists’ popular books and lectures. For example, a well-known researcher and popularizer of cosmology, Paul Davies, who was a post-doctoral student of Fred Hoyle in Cambridge University, wrote: “[…] in my opinion science offers a surer path to God than religion” (Davies 1984, p. ix).

  8. 8.

    Detailed discussions of these problems can be found in almost any textbook on contemporary cosmology. For example, see Dodelson (2003). A very readable non-technical account is given by Guth (1998).

  9. 9.

    That is to say, the BBM had to assume that the universe started in a way that the temperature everywhere was exactly the same as if it was pre-arranged.

  10. 10.

    The program of unification in fundamental physics has a long history going back at least to Maxwell ’s work on electricity and magnetism. In the context of particle physics, the most fruitful result achieved up until today is the unification of the weak and electromagnetic interactions by Abdus Salam , Sheldon Glashow , and Steven Weinberg , who were awarded the Nobel Prize in Physics in 1979 for their work. At present, no such success seems to be on the horizon for the GUT project. I recognize that the question whether unification can be analyzed as a boundary transgression is an important one but it is beyond the limits of this paper. Still, it seems reasonable to think that it should be understood as an intra-disciplinary formation, for in unification one combines two or more subdisciplines with their own separate set of entities, questions, and methods. Even though in the context of particle physics there are considerable similarities between the subdisciplines that one aims to unify, the differences are far from trivial, which explains why, as I mentioned, a consistent and empirically adequate GUT does not yet exist.

  11. 11.

    In other words, as inflation gives an account of how a small enough space that was causally connected in the early universe could become the entire observable universe, the homogeneity of temperature is not puzzling. There was enough time for radiation to equalize the temperature.

  12. 12.

    These being Perlmutter et al. (1999) for the SCP collaboration and Riess et al. (1998) for the HZS .

  13. 13.

    Here, Aν stands for “extinction,” which is the reduction in the intensity of light as it passes through the interstellar medium.

  14. 14.

    I should point out that each form of transgression is equally important for the main argument of this paper. Still, it will be noticed that I allocate more space to the third form of transgression compared to the previous two. This is both because the demonstration of the final transgression requires more textual resources than the others and also it is in the third form of transgression that we fully observe the effect which constitutes the subject matter of this paper, namely, the transformation in cosmology which brought certain questions of “meaning” within the jurisdiction of this science.

  15. 15.

    As if the value of the parameter is “tuned” by a “purposeful designer.”

  16. 16.

    Such as the charge of the electron or the value of the cosmological constant.

  17. 17.

    That is to say, the anthropic principle is required to explain the universe that we live in naturally, without invoking the existence of a “creator.”

  18. 18.

    The conceptual and technical details of this argument are beyond the scope of this paper. As my aim is not to assess Krauss ’s argument but simply to document how it represents cosmology, I will be content with stating it in most general terms.

  19. 19.

    The book by Barrow and Tipler that Ellis mentions is Barrow and Tipler (1988).

  20. 20.

    This paper received 561 citations at the time of this writing.

References

  • Albert D (2012) On the origin of everything: ‘A Universe From Nothing,’ by Lawrence M. Krauss. http://www.nytimes.com/2012/03/25/books/review/a-universe-from-nothing-by-lawrence-m-krauss.html. Accessed 18 June 2015

  • Barrow J, Tipler F (1988) The anthropic cosmological principle. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bostrom N (2007) Anthropic bias: observation selection effects in science and philosophy. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter B (1974) Large number coincidences and the anthropic principle in cosmology. In: Longair MS (ed) Confrontation of cosmological theories with observational data. Proceedings of the symposium, Krakow. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 291–298

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig WL (1988) Barrow and Tipler on the anthropic principle vs. divine design. Br J Philos Sci 39:389–395

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies P (1984) God and the new physics. Simon & Schuster, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodelson S (2003) Modern cosmology. Academic Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman J (2001) Lambda: the constant that refuses to die. Arch Hist Exact Sci 55:189–220

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis G (2011) Editorial note to: Brandon Carter, large number coincidences and the anthropic principle. Gen Relat Gravit 43:3213–3223

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin A (1989) The neglect of experiment. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Guth AH (1981) Inflationary universe: a possible solution to the horizon and flatness problems. Phys Rev D 23:347–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guth AH (1998) The inflationary universe. Basic Books, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawking SW (1983) Quantum cosmology. In: DeWitt B, Stora R (eds) Relativity, groups and topology. Les Houches, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawking SW (1984) The quantum state of the universe. Nucl Phys B 239:257–285

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawking SW (2011) The grand design. Bantam, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawking SW, Hartle JB (1983) The wave function of the universe. Phys Rev D 28:2960–2975

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubble E (1929) A relation between distance and radial velocity among extra-galactic nebulae. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 15(3):168–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ISCAP—Institute for Strings, Cosmology, and Astroparticle Physics (2015) About ISCAP. http://www.iscap.columbia.edu/pages_html/page_mission.html. Accessed 18 June 2015

  • Krauss L (2012) A universe from nothing. Free Press, New York, p 25

    Google Scholar 

  • Krauss L, Scherrer RJ (2007) The return of a static universe and the end of cosmology. Gen Relat Gravit 39:1545–1550

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liddle A (2003) An introduction to modern cosmology. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayo D (1996) Error and the growth of experimental knowledge. The Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perlmutter et al (1999) Measurements of Ω and Λ from 42 high-redshift supernovae. Astrophys J 517:565–586

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (2002) The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Riess et al (1998) Observational evidence from supernovae for an accelerating universe and a cosmological constant. Astron J 116:1009–1038

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Staley K (2011) The evidence for the top quark. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Susskind L (2006) The cosmic landscape. Back Bay Books, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Susskind L (2007) The anthropic landscape of string theory. In: Carr B (ed) Universe or multiverse. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 247–266

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (2004) The vocation lectures (edited by D. Owen and T.B. Strong). Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (2011 [1917]) Wissenschaft als Beruf. Duncker & Humblot, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Genco Guralp .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden GmbH

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Guralp, G. (2016). Cosmology and the End of Weberian Science . In: Krings, BJ., Rodríguez, H., Schleisiek, A. (eds) Scientific Knowledge and the Transgression of Boundaries. Technikzukünfte, Wissenschaft und Gesellschaft / Futures of Technology, Science and Society. Springer VS, Wiesbaden. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-14449-4_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics