Skip to main content

Second-Order False-Belief Tasks: Analysis and Formalization

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Logic, Language, Information, and Computation (WoLLIC 2016)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNTCS,volume 9803))

Abstract

We first give a coarse-grained modal-logical analysis of the four best known second-order false-belief tasks. This preliminary analysis shows that the four tasks share a common logical structure in which a crucial role is played by a “principle of inertia” which says that an agent’s belief is preserved over time unless the agent gets information to the contrary. It also reveals informational symmetries (all four possibilities inherent in the two dimensions of deception versus no-deception and change-in-world versus change-in-belief-only are realized) and reveals a rather puzzling feature common to all four tasks. We then take a closer look at how the principle of inertia is used, which leads to a fine-grained analysis in terms of perspective shifting. We formalize this analysis using a natural deduction system for hybrid logic, and show that the proof modelling the solution to the first-order Sally-Anne task is nested inside the proof modelling the second-order solution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The three other task we consider are the bake-sale task, the ice-cream task, and the puppy task; see Tables 45 and 6 in the Appendix. The ice-cream task was the very first second-order false-belief task to be used; it was introduced in 1985 by Wimmer and Perner in [14]. The bake-sale task is a variant of the ice-cream task, and, as is explained in [11], pages 323–324: “The stories were modeled after Wimmer and Perner’s (1985) “ice cream truck story”. In contrast to their stories, we made sure that the beliefs of the two main protagonists in the story did not overlap, both at first-order and second-order level: each protagonist had his or her own distinct belief which was different from that of the other protagonist, as well as from the belief of the participants.” The puppy task was introduced in 1994 in [19], again as a simplification of Wimmer and Perner’s ice-cream task.

  2. 2.

    Some stories use more times than this: the bake-sale story, for example, makes use of (at least) four. But the sequence \(t_0\), \(t_1\), and \(t_2\) constitutes the narrated time of the story, and here it is pointless to distinguish the times when Sam and Maria learn that there are no chocolate cookies for sale.

  3. 3.

    In this section we adopt the following convention: belief-states that are part of this common pattern are typeset in bold (and displayed in blue in the online version), other belief-states are typeset in normal font.

  4. 4.

    Note that rows 4,9,14,19 in Table 3 have the same form , and are part of the common reasoning pattern leading to the correct answer, hence they are typeset in bold (and blue in the online version). Similarly, rows 2,7,12,17 have the same form , , and are part of the common reasoning pattern, so they are also bold (and blue). That is, the information in these rows is part of the experimental design, and is intended to ensure that agent x ends up having a false belief about the belief of agent y.

  5. 5.

    The distinction between tasks that do and do not involve deception is considered important for first-order false beliefs, as deception in a story may signal the relevance of detecting falsehood. But it has been little discussed for second-order tasks; see [13], especially pages 48–49, for discussion and pointers to the literature.

  6. 6.

    Which is why this information is not typeset in bold (and why in the online version, it is not in blue), and also why in Table 2 (the coarse-grained reasoning analysis) it has been put in parentheses.

  7. 7.

    There are some interesting possibilities here: we could make our formalization more fine-grained by taking some nominals to stand for times, or go two-dimensional by taking nominals to stand for person-time pairs. But here we stick with the simpler setup just defined, as it has the same granularity as Stenning and Van Lambalgen’s work on first-order false-belief tasks, cf. [18], pages 251–259.

  8. 8.

    Natural deduction was originally developed to model mathematical argumentation, but there is now some experimental backing for the claim that it is a mechanism underlying human deductive reasoning more generally; see [16]. One of the reasons we chose hybrid logic for our analysis (rather than, say, a multi-agent doxastic logic) was because of its well-behaved natural deduction systems; see [5].

  9. 9.

    Incidentally, when using the Term rule we make at least one assumption c, but we can make several, and this is often necessary to drive the proof through.

  10. 10.

    The Name rule tells us that if we can prove the information \(\phi \) by adopting some arbitrary perspective c, then \(\phi \) also holds from the original perspective. As we won’t use this rule in our analysis, we refer to [5] for further discussion.

  11. 11.

    Indicated by the premisses \(\phi _{1} \ldots \phi _{n}\) listed just above the horizontal line in the statement of Term given in Fig. 1.

  12. 12.

    A subtlety worth emphasising is that (as is stated in Fig. 1) the assumptions \({[} \phi _{1} {]} \ldots {[} \phi _{n} {]}\) must all be satisfaction statements, otherwise the rule is not sound. We refer the reader to [17] and Chap. 4 of [5] for further discussion.

  13. 13.

    As we mentioned earlier, “belief formation” (and “belief manipulation”) is terminology we have borrowed from [18], and we discuss them in more detail shortly. As for the belief formations principles themselves, we have already met Principle \((\mathsf{D})\) which says if we believe that something is false, then we don’t believe it. Principle (P1) states that a belief in \(\phi \) may be formed as a result of seeing \(\phi \); this is principle (9.2) in [18], page 251. Principle (P2) is (pretty clearly) a principle of inertia: a belief that the predicate l is true is preserved from a time t to its successor \(t+1\), unless it is believed that the marble moved at t. This is essentially Principle (9.11) from [18], page 253, and axiom \([A_5]\) in [1], page 20. Principle (P3) encodes the information that seeing the marble being moved is the only way a belief that the marble is being moved can be acquired. Obviously this is not a general truth, but the point of the formalization is simply to capture Peter’s reasoning in the Sally-Anne scenario.

  14. 14.

    As we remarked earlier, we do this to ‘compile down’ the simple propositional reasoning involved. Strictly speaking, deducing \(B\phi \) from \(S\phi \) requires us to apply the propositional rule of modus ponens to \(S\phi \rightarrow B\phi \). Using the belief formation principles as additional natural deduction rules enables us to omit such steps and reduce the size of the proof tree.

  15. 15.

    Stenning and Van Lambalgen do not analyse second-order false-belief tasks.

  16. 16.

    So we are adding natural deduction machinery for the minimal modal logic K and thus treating B as a full-fledged modal operator. In this paper we won’t discuss the model-theoretic changes required — but we do believe that the fact that a semantic enrichment is called for at this point adds weight to our argument that the transition from first- to second-order reasoning involves conceptual change.

  17. 17.

    Indeed, our analysis allows us to tentatively indicate the shift in complexity. The LCD fragment is np-complete. By adding BM we have moved to a pspace-hard modal logic. So our analysis of the first-order Sally-Anne task is carried out in computationally simpler logic than the second-order case (assuming p \(\not =\) np).

  18. 18.

    Our formalization does suggest a hypothesis which may be empirically testable. Although we have talked of acquiring second-order competency, to acquire (something like) the BM rule is to acquire a fully recursive competency. That is, once the child has acquired BM, there should be nothing more to learn, for the rule covers the third, fourth, fifth, ..., and all higher-order levels. That is, we suspect that false-belief competency comes in two stages for typically developing children: first-order competency (at around the age of four) and all the rest (at around the age of six). But designing an experiment to test this is likely to be difficult. Apart from anything else, higher levels of reasoning impose heavy cognitive loads very fast, and it is unclear how such performance effects could be disentangled experimentally.

References

  1. Arkoudas, K., Bringsjord, S.: Toward formalizing common-sense psychology: an analysis of the false-belief task. In: Ho, T.-B., Zhou, Z.-H. (eds.) PRICAI 2008. LNCS (LNAI), vol. 5351, pp. 17–29. Springer, Heidelberg (2008)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  2. Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A.M., Frith, U.: Does the autistic child have a ‘theory of mind’? Cognition 21(1), 37–46 (1985)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Baron-Cohen, S., O’Riordan, M., Stone, V., Jones, R., Plaisted, K.: Recognition of faux pas by normally developing children and children with Asperger syndrome or high-functioning autism. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 29(5), 407–418 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Bolander, T.: Seeing is believing: formalising false-belief tasks in dynamic epistemic logic. In: Herzig, A., Lorini, E. (eds.) Proceedings of the European Conference on Social Intelligence (ECSI-2014), pp. 87–107. Toulouse University, France, IRIT-CNRS (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Braüner, T.: Hybrid Logic and its Proof-Theory. Applied Logic Series, vol. 37. Springer, Heidelberg (2011)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Braüner, T.: Hybrid-logical reasoning in the Smarties and Sally-Anne tasks. J. Logic Lang. Inf. 23, 415–439 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Braüner, T.: Hybrid-logical reasoning in the Smarties and Sally-Anne tasks: what goes wrong when incorrect responses are given? In: Proceedings of the 37th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, pp. 273–278. Cognitive Science Society, Pasadena, California (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Braüner, T., Blackburn, P., Polyanskaya, I.: Recursive belief manipulation and second-order false-beliefs. In: Proceedings of the 38th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society. Cognitive Science Society, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, USA (2016, to appear)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Fitting, M.: Modal proof theory. In: Blackburn, P., van Benthem, J., Wolter, F. (eds.) Handbook of Modal Logic, pp. 85–138. Elsevier, New York (2007)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  10. Hale, C., Tager-Flusberg, H.: The influence of language on theory of mind: a training study. Dev. Sci. 6, 346–359 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Hollebrandse, B., van Hout, A., Hendriks, P.: Children’s first and second-order false-belief reasoning in a verbal and a low-verbal task. Synthese 191, 321–333 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Miller, S.: Children’s understanding of second-order mental states. Psychol. Bull. 135, 749–773 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Miller, S.: Theory of Mind: Beyond the Preschool Years. Psychology Press, New York (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Perner, J., Wimmer, H.: “John thinks that Mary thinks that..": attribution of second-order beliefs by 5-to 10-year-old children. J. Exp. Child Psychol. 39, 437–471 (1985)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Polyanskaya, I., Braüner, T., Blackburn, P.: Linguistic recursion and Autism Spectrum Disorder. Manuscript (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Rips, L.: Logical approaches to human deductive reasoning. In: Adler, J., Rips, L. (eds.) Reasoning: Studies of Human Inference and Its Foundations, pp. 187–205. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2008)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  17. Seligman, J.: The logic of correct description. In: de Rijke, M. (ed.) Advances in Intensional Logic. Applied Logic Series, vol. 7, pp. 107–135. Kluwer, Dordrecht (1997)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  18. Stenning, K., van Lambalgen, M.: Human Reasoning and Cognitive Science. MIT Press, Cambridge (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Sullivan, K., Zaitchik, D., Tager-Flusberg, H.: Preschoolers can attribute second-order beliefs. Dev. Psychol. 30, 395–402 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Szymanik, J., Meijering, B., Verbrugge, R.: Using intrinsic complexity of turn-taking games to predict participants’ reaction times. In: Knauff, M., Pauen, M., Sebanz, N., Wachsmuth, I. (eds.) Proceedings of the 35th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, pp. 1426–1432. Cognitive Science Society, Austin (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Wellman, H., Cross, D., Watson, J.: Meta-analysis of theory-of-mind development: the truth about false-belief. Child Dev. 72, 655–684 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank the referees for their valuable comments and questions. The authors acknowledge the funding received from the VELUX FOUNDATION for the project Hybrid-Logical Proofs at Work in Cognitive Psychology (VELUX 33305).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Torben Braüner .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix

Appendix

The Appendix contains the coarse-grained reasoning for the four tasks (Table 2), the table listing their information content (Table 3), the texts of the bake-sale, ice-cream and puppy tasks (Tables 4, 5 and 6 respectively) and the formalization of the first-order and second-order Sally-Anne tasks (Figs. 3 and 4).

Table 2. A coarse-grained analysis of second-order false-belief tasks in terms of belief-states
Table 3. Zero-order, first-order and second-order information in the tasks
Table 4. The bake-sale task (quoted from [11], pictures and some questions omitted)
Table 5. The ice-cream task (introduced in [14], quoted from [12], a question omitted)
Table 6. The puppy task (introduced in [19], quoted from [12], some questions omitted)
Fig. 3.
figure 3

Formalization of the child’s correct response in the first-order Sally-Anne task

Fig. 4.
figure 4

Formalization of the child’s correct response in the second-order Sally-Anne task

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this paper

Cite this paper

Braüner, T., Blackburn, P., Polyanskaya, I. (2016). Second-Order False-Belief Tasks: Analysis and Formalization. In: Väänänen, J., Hirvonen, Å., de Queiroz, R. (eds) Logic, Language, Information, and Computation. WoLLIC 2016. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 9803. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-52921-8_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-52921-8_9

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-662-52920-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-52921-8

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics