Skip to main content

A Model-Theoretic Reconstruction of Type-Theoretic Semantics for Anaphora

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Formal Grammar (FG 2017)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNTCS,volume 10686))

Included in the following conference series:

Abstract

I present an analysis of the interpretation of anaphora that takes concepts from type-theoretic semantics, in particular the use of the \(\varSigma \) and \(\varPi \) dependent type constructors, and incorporates them into a model-theoretic framework. The analysis makes use of (parametrically) polymorphic lexical entries. The key ideas are that, in the simplest case, eventualities can play the role that proof objects do in type-theoretic semantics; that more complex, compositionally-defined, structures can play that role in other cases; and that pronouns can be modelled by context-dependent functions from proof objects of the preceding discourse (in this sense) to entities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 44.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 60.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    \(\varSigma \) can also be used to give the meaning of conjunction, and \(\varPi \) implication; this is reflected in the lexical entries given in Fig. 1. Limitations of space prevent any further consideration of these connections here.

  2. 2.

    Here and throughout the paper, a dot following a variable binder will often be used instead of parentheses to indicate unbounded scope to the right.

  3. 3.

    One option, therefore, is to change the model theory so that (5) would be interpreted in the desired way. This, explicitly, is the approach taken in Dynamic Predicate Logic (DPL) [8]. Discourse Representation Theory (DRT) [13] and File Change Semantics (FCS) [10] take a similar approach.

  4. 4.

    By this, I mean that meanings will be given as expressions of a logical language, which are taken to be dispensable in favour of their interpretations in a model (as in [16]), which is where the ‘real’ semantics is. Expressions of the language of type theory are not understood this way in TTS; see [14] and [18], Sect. 2.27.

  5. 5.

    In the type annotations, here and throughout the rest of the paper, brackets are omitted where possible, on the understanding that both \(\times \) and associate to the right and that \(\times \) binds more tightly than .

  6. 6.

    The same issue prompted [2] to switch from treating common nouns as type-denoting to predicate-denoting.

  7. 7.

    In the rest of the paper this will be referred to as ‘the null context’, and will generally be assumed.

  8. 8.

    This corresponds closely to the truth definition for DRT proposed in [12], p. 149.

  9. 9.

    Some speakers may allow an interpretation of (24) on which a donkey takes wider scope than negation. In that case, the pronoun could anaphorically refer back to the donkey.

  10. 10.

    Figure 1 defines VP negation, which is derived from sentential negation in the obvious way. The VP formulation is more transparent in terms of compositional semantics, and also makes Giles available for anaphoric reference.

  11. 11.

    As stated, \(\lambda b.[[b]_1]_0\) is also a possible resolution function, which would have it varying with farmers rather than donkeys, which is obviously not a possible reading of (25). This reading could be ruled out by tweaking the lexical entry for every, but only at the cost of ruling out interpretations that we do want when we have an embedded clause. The mechanism for ruling out violations of ‘Principle B’ must come from somewhere else.

References

  1. Barwise, J., Cooper, R.: Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguist. Philos. 4(2), 159–219 (1981)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Bekki, D.: Representing anaphora with dependent types. In: Asher, N., Soloviev, S. (eds.) LACL 2014. LNCS, vol. 8535, pp. 14–29. Springer, Heidelberg (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-43742-1_2

    Google Scholar 

  3. Dekker, P.: Predicate logic with anaphora. In: Harvey, M., Samelmann, L. (eds.) Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory, vol. 4, pp. 79–95 (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  4. van Eijck, J.: Incremental dynamics. J. Logic Lang. Inf. 10, 319–351 (2001)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Emms, M.: Polymorphic quantifiers. In: Stokhof, M., Torenvliet, L. (eds.) Proceedings of the Seventh Amsterdam Colloquium. Institute for Language, Logic and Information, Amsterdam (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Geach, P.T.: Reference and Generality. Contemporary Philosophy. Cornell University Press, Ithaca (1962)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Girard, J.Y.: The system \(F\) of variable types, fifteen years later. Theor. Comput. Sci. 45, 159–192 (1986)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Groenendijk, J., Stokhof, M.: Dynamic predicate logic. Linguist. Philos. 14(1), 39–100 (1991)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. de Groote, P.: Towards a Montagovian account of dynamics. In: Gibson, M., Howell, J. (eds.) Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory, vol. 16, pp. 1–16 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Heim, I.: The semantics of definite and indefinite nouns phrases. Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachussetts, Amherst (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Jacobson, P.: Towards a variable-free semantics. Linguist. Philos. 22(2), 117–184 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  12. Kamp, H., van Genabith, J., Reyle, U.: Discourse representation theory. In: Gabbay, D.M., Guenther, F. (eds.) Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. 15, 2nd edn, pp. 125–394. Springer, Dordrecht (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0485-5_3

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  13. Kamp, H., Reyle, U.: From Discourse to Logic. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 42. Springer, Dordrecht (1993). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1616-1

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  14. Luo, Z.: Formal semantics in modern type theories: is it model-theoretic, proof-theoretic, or both? In: Asher, N., Soloviev, S. (eds.) LACL 2014. LNCS, vol. 8535, pp. 177–188. Springer, Heidelberg (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-43742-1_14

    Google Scholar 

  15. Martin-Löf, P.: An intuitionistic theory of types: predicative part. In: Rose, H., Shepherdson, J. (eds.) Logic Colloquium 1973. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 80, pp. 73–118. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1975)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Montague, R.: The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In: Suppes, P., Moravcsik, J., Hintikka, J. (eds.) Approaches to Natural Language, pp. 221–242. D. Reidel, Dordrecht (1973)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  17. Nouwen, R.: On dependent pronouns and dynamic semantics. J. Philos. Logic 36(2), 123–154 (2007)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Ranta, A.: Type-Theoretical Grammar. Indices, vol. 1. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1994)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Reynolds, J.C.: Polymorphism is not set-theoretic. In: Kahn, G., MacQueen, D.B., Plotkin, G. (eds.) SDT 1984. LNCS, vol. 173, pp. 145–156. Springer, Heidelberg (1984). https://doi.org/10.1007/3-540-13346-1_7

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  20. Steedman, M.: Taking Scope. MIT Press, Cambridge (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Sundholm, G.: Proof theory and meaning. In: Gabbay, D., Guenther, F. (eds.) Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. 3, pp. 471–506. D. Reidel, Dordrecht (1986)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  22. Tanaka, R., Nakano, Y., Bekki, D.: Constructive generalized quantifiers revisited. In: Nakano, Y., Satoh, K., Bekki, D. (eds.) JSAI-isAI 2013. LNCS (LNAI), vol. 8417, pp. 115–124. Springer, Cham (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-10061-6_8

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew Gotham .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer-Verlag GmbH Germany

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Gotham, M. (2018). A Model-Theoretic Reconstruction of Type-Theoretic Semantics for Anaphora. In: Foret, A., Muskens, R., Pogodalla, S. (eds) Formal Grammar . FG 2017. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 10686. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-56343-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-56343-4_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-662-56342-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-56343-4

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics