Skip to main content

Epistemic Consequences of Two Different Strategies for Decomposing Biological Networks

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
EPSA Philosophical Issues in the Sciences

Abstract

It is the mission of systems biology to investigate large biological networks (paradigmatic of cellular extension), and to explain their dynamics by means of mathematical models. Since these networks are far too complex to be modeled directly, they first must be decomposed into subnetworks of mathematically manageable size. This is often done by breaking the network down into quasi-independent modules. Different modularization strategies are applied, relying on functional (physiological) or on structural criteria (related to the topology of the network). This paper demonstrates that choosing a modularization strategy has far-reaching epistemic consequences: The modularization method predefines the kind of model that can be used to describe the network; by this it also predefines the explanatory goals that can be followed successfully. I further challenge the standard view that decomposition of a network according to structural criteria is neutral (while functional decomposition gives a biased picture) and demonstrate that also the choice of a structural criterion introduces a bias.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Stochastic models may serve as a more realistic substitute for kinetic models (which counterfactually assume continuity of matter). In these, reaction events, e.g., the transition of a particular molecule of a given molecular species, replace the reaction rates (Rao et al. 2002).

  2. 2.

    See Krohs (2009b) for a reconstruction of theory structure in such cases.

  3. 3.

    The citric acid cycle may serve as an example. It is delineated functionally (Krohs 2004: 173) and consequently forms a functional module. But each metabolic intermediate of the cycle is, besides its two edges within the cycle, also involved in many reactions that do not belong to the cycle but link it to other functional modules and help regulate the size of the pools of each of the intermediates (Kornberg 1965; Owen et al. 2002). By an analysis of a discrete model of the network, the external interactions are judged to be stronger than the internal ones. The functional module of the citric acid cycle is therefore not a structural module (Krohs 2009a).

  4. 4.

    As mentioned in Section 15.2, it is often the other way around, namely that only a discrete model can be based on a given data set and that it is difficult to find goals that are compatible with this modeling strategy (see also Krohs and Callebaut 2007).

  5. 5.

    Including stochastic approaches as mentioned in note 1.

  6. 6.

    It may, however, count as a mechanistic explanation of the dynamic of the structural module. But as long as this dynamic is not itself interpreted physiologically – and thus the structural framework is given up in favor of a functional one – it is hard to see the biological relevance of such an explanation.

  7. 7.

    On of the main problems being a high percentage of false positives in the analysis of interactions (Deane et al. 2002; Albert 2005).

References

  • Albert R (2005) Scale-free networks in cell biology. J Cell Sci 118:4947–4957

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Abrahamsen Ȧ (2005) Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 33:421–441

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Richardson RC (1993) Discovering complexity: decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Boogerd FC, Bruggeman FJ, Hofmeyr J-HS, Westerhoff HV (eds) (2007) Systems biology: Philosophical foundations. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruggeman, FJ, Westerhoff HV (2006) The nature of systems biology. Trends Microbiol 15:45–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chavez M, Albert R, Sontag ED (2005) Robustness and fragility of Boolean models for genetic regulatory networks. J Theoret Biol 235:431–449

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF (2001) Role functions, mechanisms, and hierarchy. Philos Sci 68:53–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden L, Craver CF (2002) Strategies in the interfield discovery of the mechanism of protein synthesis. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 33:1–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deane CM, Salwiński Ł, Xenarios I, Eisenberg D (2002) Protein interactions: Two methods for assessment of the reliability of high throughput observations. Mol Cell Proteom 1:349–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman N (2004) Inferring cellular networks using probabilistic graphical models. Science 303:799–805

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keseler IM, Collado-Vides J, Gama-Castro S, Ingraham J, Paley S, Paulsen IT, Peralta-Gil M, Karp PD (2005) EcoCyc: A comprehensive database resource for Escherichia coli. Nucl Acid Res 33(Database Issue):D334–D337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornberg HL (1965) Anaplerotic sequences in microbial metabolism. Angewandte Chem Int Edn 4:558–565

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koza JR, Mydlowec W, Lanza G, Yu J, Keane MA (2002) Automated reverse engineering of metabolic pathways from observed data by means of genetic programming. In Kitano H (ed) Foundations of systems biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 95–121

    Google Scholar 

  • Krohs U (2004) Eine Theorie biologischer Theorien: Status und Gehalt von Funktionsaussagen und informationstheoretischen Modellen. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Krohs, U (2009a) The cost of modularity. In: Krohs U, Kroes P (eds) Functions in biological and artificial worlds: Comparative philosophical perspectives. MIT Press, Cambridge MA, pp 259–276

    Google Scholar 

  • Krohs U (2009b). Structure and coherence of two-model-descriptions of technical artefacts. Technē: Res Philos Technol 13:150–161

    Google Scholar 

  • Krohs U, Callebaut W (2007) Data without models merging with models without data. In: Boogerd FC, Bruggeman FJ, Hofmeyr J-HS, Westerhoff HV (eds) Systems biology: Philosophical foundations. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 181–213

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer P (2004) Activities and causation: The metaphysics and epistemology of mechanisms. Int Stud Philos Sci 18:27–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer P, Darden L, Craver CF (2000) Thinking about mechanisms. Philos Sci 67:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milo R, Shen-Orr S, Itzkovitz S, Kashtan N, Chklovskii D, Alon U (2002) Network motifs: Simple building blocks of complex networks. Science 298:824–827

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley M, Dupré J (2005) Fundamental issues in systems biology. BioEssays 27:1270–1276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Onami S, Kyoda KM, Morohashi M, Kitano H (2002) The DBRF method for inferring a gene network from large-scale steady-state gene expression data. In Kitano H (ed) Foundations of systems biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 59–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen OE, Kalhan SC, Hanson RW (2002) The key role of anaplerosis and cataplerosis for citric acid cycle function. J Biol Chem 277:30409–30412

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palsson B (2006) Systems biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papin JA, Reed JL, Palsson BO (2004). Hierarchical thinking in network biology: The unbiased modularization of biochemical networks. Trends Biochem Sci 29:641–647

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rao CV, Wolf DM, Arkin AP (2002) Control, exploitation and tolerance of intracellular noise. Nature 420:231–237

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rohwer JM, Schuster S, Westerhoff HV (1996) How to recognize monofunctional units in a metabolic system. J Theoret Biol 179:213–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner KF (1998) Genes, behavior, and developmental emergentism: One process, indivisible? Philos Sci 65:209–252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shen-Orr SS, Milo R, Mangan S, Alon U (2002) Network motifs in the transcriptional regulation network of Escherichia coli. Nat Genet 31:64–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1969) The sciences of the artificial, 3rd edn. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Westerhoff HV, Palsson BO (2004) The evolution of molecular biology into systems biology. Nat Biotechnol 22:1249–1252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Su C, Peregrin-Alvarez JM, Butland G, Phanse S, Fong V, Emili A, Parkinson J (2008) Bacteriome.org – An integrated protein interaction database for E. coli. Nucl Acid Res 36(Database issue): D632–D636

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

Support during the later stages of this work by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG), grant KR3662/1–1, is gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ulrich Krohs .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Krohs, U. (2010). Epistemic Consequences of Two Different Strategies for Decomposing Biological Networks. In: Suárez, M., Dorato, M., Rédei, M. (eds) EPSA Philosophical Issues in the Sciences. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3252-2_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics