Skip to main content

Resources for a Dialectical Legal Semiotics?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Prospects of Legal Semiotics

Abstract

This study discusses the possibilities for developing a model of legal semiotics based upon the distinctly dialectical theories of language, culture and society contained in the writings of Hegel and Theodor Adorno. It builds upon, and contributes to, a growing interest in Hegel’s theory of language more generally. For both Hegel and Adorno, it is not possible to develop a viable theory of culture, social integration and cultural/intellectual development occurring over various transitional stages, without attending to how the semiotic dimensions of human experience operate. The routine employment of various signs associated with, for example “law”, “legality”, “legal procedure” etc. and the relations between them, help generate, sustain and modify an overall, and collectively shared, interpretative framework. This study focuses upon only three of the host of possible themes that a Hegelian semiotics of law could usefully address. These are: the interpretation of core semiotics distinctions; the implications of the mediating role played by signs; and, thirdly, the application to our lived-experience of legal signs of a semiotically informed methodology of “immanent criticism”. The latter provides an approach to the conduct of advanced research into contextual aspects of semiotic themes, whose potential as a self-critical resource for “law and semiotics” has yet to be adequately realised. The Hegelian tradition rejects the idea that the relationship between legal signs and the signified is essentially arbitrary, treating this interpretation as itself an arbitrary and ideologically-loaded construct that articulates historically specific pathologies of late modern social, cultural and political relations. Instead, this scholarly tradition seeks to expose from within the zone of our concrete lived-experience of signs remnants of the mutual implication of these two strata. Its critical methodology aims to analyse contradictions between the implications of law’s normative expressions, and the impact of the actions of legal institutions upon specific groups of human subjects. Such a critical approach contrasts actual institutional outcomes with the implications of the norms they continue to rely upon to secure their legitimacy. This approach is only possible, however, once we grasp the significance of the potentially dialectical, that is mutually defining, nature of the sign/signified relationship. Without this recognition, legal semiotics risks self-imposed imprisonment within an artificially disconnected, experientially impoverished and narcissistic sphere of “cultural studies”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Adorno, T. W. 1956. Quasi una Fantasia, Essays on Modern Music, tr. Rodney Livingstone. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, T. W. 1971. Die Actualitat der Philosophie. In Die Frühschrifen. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, T. W. 1973. Thesen über die Sprache des Philosophen. In Die Frühschrifen. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, T. W. 1974. Henkel, Krug und frühe Erfhrung. In Noten zue Literatur. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, T. W. Negative Dialectics, 2001 revised English translation by Dennis Redmond at: http://www.efn.org/~dredmond/MM3.html

  • Adorno, T. W. Minima Moralia, 2005 revised English translation by Dennis Redmond at: http://www.efn.org/~dredmond/MM3.html

  • Adorno, Theodor W. and Horkheimer, Max. 1972. Dialectic of Enlightenment. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodammer, T. 1969. Hegels Deutung der Sprache. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brockmeier, J. 1990. Language, Thought and Writing: Hegel After Deconstruction and the Linguistic Turn. Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain, 21–22, 30–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burbidge, J. 1981. On Hegel’s Logic: Fragments of a Commentary. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burbidge, J. 1982. Language and Recognition. In ed. M. Westphal, Method and Speculation in Hegel’s Phenomenology Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities, 85–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, T. 1989. Hegel, Derrida, and the Sign. In ed. H. Silverman Derrida and Deconstruction. New York, NY: Routledge, 77–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, T. 2000. The Purloined Hegel: Semiology in the Thought of Saussure and Derrida. History of the Human Sciences, 13(4), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, A. B. 2000. Hegel on Language, Citizenship, and the Educational Function of the Workplace: The Marxist Challenge. Owl of Minerva, 32(1), 21–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coltman, K. 1966. Gadamer, Hegel and The Middle of Language. Philosophy Today, 40, 151–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, D.J.1973. Language in the Philosophy of Hegel, NY:Den Haag.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Boer, K. 2001. The Infinite Movement of Self-Conception and Its Inconceivable Finitude: Hegel on Logos and Language. Dialogue, 40, 75–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. 1976. Of Grammatology, tr. G. Spivak. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. 1982. The Pit and Pyramid: Introduction to Hegel’s Semiology. In Margins of Philosophy, tr. Alan Bass. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 69–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster, S. 2006. Adorno: The Recovery of Experience. New York, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, S. 1994. Hegel on Saying and Showing. Journal of Value Inquiry, 28(2), 151–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, I. 1982. The Linguistic Basis of Truth for Hegel. Man and World 15, 285–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. 1969. In ed. Werke. Science of Logic, tr. A. V. Miller. New York, NY: Humanity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. 1970–1971. In ed. Werke, Eva Moldenhauer, and Karl Markus, 2 vols. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. 1975. In ed. Werke. Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind, tr. W. Wallace. New York, NY and Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeister, J., ed. 1936. Dokumente zu Hegels Entwicklung. Stuttgart: From-mann, reissued, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamb, D. 1980. Language and Perception in Hegel and Wittgenstein. New York, NY: St. Martin’s.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, C. F. 2006. Language and Metaphysics: The Dialectics of Hegel’s Speculative Proposition. In ed. J. O. Surber, Hegel and language. Albany, NY: SUNY, 55–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz and Hegel on Language. 1973. In eds. J. O’Malley, K. Algozin, and F. R. Weiss, Hegel and the History of Philosophy, The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwith, K. 1965. Hegel und die Sprache. Die neue Rundschau, 76, 278–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, K. D. 2001. Hegel and the Symbolic Mediation of Spirit. New York, NY: SUNY.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCumber, J. 1993. The Company of Words: Hegel, Language, and Systematic Philosophy. Evanston, IL: Northwestern.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCumber, J. 2003. A Question of Origin: Hegel’s Privileging of Spoken over Written Language. Bulletin of Hegel of Great Britain, 47/48, 50–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nancy, J. L. 2001. The Speculative Remark, tr. C. Suprenant. Stanford, IL: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuzzo, A. 2006. The Language of Hegel’s Speculative Philosophy. In ed. J. O. Surber, Hegel and Language. Albany, NY: SUNY, 75–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearson, G., and Salter, M. 1999. Getting Public Law Back into a Critical Condition: The Rule of Law as a Source for Immanent Critique. Journal of Social and Legal Studies, 8(4), 483–508.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, J. D. 1997. The Root of Humanity: Hegel on Communication and Language. In eds. D. Klemm and G. Zöller, Figuring the Self: Subject, Absolute and Others in Classical German Philosophy. Albany, NY: SUNY, 227–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, J. 2006. Objective Language and Scientific Truth in Hegel. In ed. J. O. Surber, Hegel and Language. Albany, NY: SUNY, 95–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salter, Michael. 1992. Laws of Language in Hegel’s Semiology. International Journal of Law and Semiotics, 5(14), 165–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salter, M., and Shaw, J. 1992. Towards a Critical Theory of Constitutional Law: Hegel’s Contribution. In ed. Michael Salter, Hegel and Law. Aldershot: Ashgate, 90–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salter, M., Shaw, J.J.A. 1994.Towards a Critical Theory of Constitutional Law: Hegel’s Contribution, Journal of Law and Society, 21(4 ), 464–486

    Google Scholar 

  • Saussure, F. 1983. Course in General Linguistics, tr. R. Harris. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schalow, F. 1993. The Question of Being and the Recovery of Language within Hegelian Thought. Owl of Minerva, 24(2), 163–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, F. 1961. Hegel’s Philosophie der Sprache. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 9, 1479–1486.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, J. 1966. Das Problem der Sprache Bei Hegel. Stuttgart: Kohlhanner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. 1974. Sentences Against Sentences: An Aspect of the Hegelian Dialectic. Dialectis and Humanism, 1, 67–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. 1987. U-Topian Hegel: Dialectic and Its Other in Post-structuralism. The German Quarterly, 60, 237–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. 1994. The Language of Mastery and the Mastery of Language: The Recognition of Rhetoric in Hegel. Clio, 23(4), 377–394.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stähler, T. 2003. Does Hegel Privilege Speech over Writing?: A Critique of Jacques Derrida. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 11(2), 191–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Surber, J. O. 1975. Hegel’s Speculative Sentence. Hegel-Studien, 10, 210–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Surber, J. O., ed. 2006. Hegel and Language. Albany, NY: SUNY.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Salter .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Salter, M. (2010). Resources for a Dialectical Legal Semiotics?. In: Wagner, A., Broekman, J. (eds) Prospects of Legal Semiotics. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9343-1_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics