Skip to main content

The Value Space of Meaningful Relations

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Human-Environment Relations

Abstract

We can construe the ‘value-space’ constituted by humans and their ­environments in a variety of ways. In mainstream environmental philosophy a preferred way of construing this space is as a collection of intrinsically valuable items, both human and non-human. On this view, environmental decision-making should be concerned with the maintaining and fostering of intrinsic value. After rehearsing a number of objections to this view, an alternative construal of the value-space is offered, which centres on the concept of ‘meaningful relations’. An account of this concept is given, along with a sketch of the value system that forms its backdrop. ‘Meaningful relations’, it is argued, is a unifying concept that characterises ­evolutionary and ecological relations as well as cultural ones. On this alternative view, environmental decision-making should be concerned with the continuation of meaning rather than the preservation of value.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is possible to imagine someone mounting the counter-argument that ‘meaning talk’ can in ­principle be reduced to, or translated into ‘value talk’. But aside from noting the point, no attempt will be made to do justice to such a rejoinder within the scope of the present paper.

  2. 2.

    I assume throughout a ‘secular’ worldview, along lines indicated in Holland (2009).

  3. 3.

    See O’Neill (1992) for a classic account of the various senses that may attach to the term ‘intrinsic value’.

  4. 4.

    Partisans of intrinsic value are not insensitive to this point: ‘value seeps out into the system’, as Rolston (2001: 145) has it.

  5. 5.

    In what follows, it will be argued that such heroic but un-demonstrable claims about the overall value of the natural world are unnecessary.

  6. 6.

    More recently, it is perhaps David Cooper (2003) who has done most to rescue the concept of meaning from the prison of language to which many philosophers would confine it.

  7. 7.

    Interestingly, he identifies fanaticism – surrender of the self to something trans-individual – as a flawed response to these anxieties.

  8. 8.

    By contrast, to discover that there is after all ‘a meaning’ to life, or that there is such a thing as ‘the meaning of life’, could be regarded as an extremely depressing prospect indeed.

  9. 9.

    It should be stressed that normative judgements are here understood to be fully fallible and open to challenge. It is only some subjectivist readings of moral judgement that misguidedly render them immune to challenge – and in the process deprive them of any normative force.

  10. 10.

    To say all this is to do little more than rehearse arguments to be found in Plato, Aristotle and the Stoics. Plato’s stress on ‘thumos’ has already been noted, while it is Aristotle who draws attention to the key role played by the intellectual virtues of wisdom and understanding. The Stoics, for their part, laid stress on the ‘intelligibility’ of the cosmos. In order to ‘follow nature’ – their key maxim – one had to grasp its meaning (‘logos’).

References

  • Attfield, R. (1987). A theory of value and obligation. London: Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Attfield, R. (2001). Postmodernism, value and objectivity. Environmental Values, 10, 145–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Attfield, R. (2006). Creation, evolution and meaning. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blythe, R. (1982). From the headlands. London: Chatto & Windus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blythe, R. (1986). Divine landscapes. Harmondsworth: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, D. E. (1992). The idea of environment. In D. E. Cooper & J. A. Palmer (Eds.), The environment in question (pp. 165–180). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, D. E. (2003). Meaning. Chesham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deakin, R. (2007). Wildwood: A journey through trees. London: Hamish Hamilton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. C. (2005). With respect for nature. New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland, A. (2009). Darwin and the meaning in life. Environmental Values, 18, 503–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F. (1922). Ethics and the economic interpretation. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 36, 454–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, K. (1952). King Solomon’s ring: New light on animal ways. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mabey, R. (1996). Flora Britannica. London: Sinclair-Stevenson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mabey, R. (2000). Country matters. London: Pimlico.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1874). Nature. In J. S. Mill, Three essays on religion. London: Longmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, J. (1992). The varieties of intrinsic value. The Monist, 75, 119–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, J. (1993). Ecology, policy and politics. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, J., Holland, A., & Light, A. (2008). Environmental values. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rackham, O. (1986). The history of the countryside. London: Dent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, H. (1992). Disvalues in nature. The Monist, 75, 250–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, H. (2001). Challenges in environmental ethics. In M. E. Zimmerman et al. (Eds.), Environmental philosophy: From animal rights to radical ecology (3rd ed., pp. 126–146). Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tillich, P. (1962). The courage to be. London: Fontana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1992). Must a concern for the environment be centred on human beings? In C. C. W. Taylor (Ed.), Ethics and the environment (pp. 60–68). Oxford: Corpus Christi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Youatt, R. (2008). Counting species: Biopower and the global biodiversity census. Environmental Values, 17, 393–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alan Holland .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Holland, A. (2012). The Value Space of Meaningful Relations. In: Brady, E., Phemister, P. (eds) Human-Environment Relations. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2825-7_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics