Skip to main content

Was There a Cartesian Experimentalism in 1660s France?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Cartesian Empiricisms

Part of the book series: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 31))

Abstract

In order to determine if there existed an experimentalist Cartesianism in France in the 1660s, I concentrate on Jacques Rohault and address the three following questions. (1) Is there a difference in the way Descartes and Rohault deal with experiments? I state that there is no doctrinal difference between them: the experiments they carry out are of the same order; they attribute the same epistemological functions to them; they share the same ontology. The main difference between them is that, unlike Descartes, Rohault made experiments a means of popularization of the Cartesian philosophy. (2) How does Rohault treat experiments in his Mercredis? Studying quite closely the evolution that led to the greater priority attributed to experiments in the scientific circles that prefigure the Académie des sciences, I show that, in 1660s France, the treatment Rohault give to experiments in his Mercredis is exceeded by the radical experimentalism of the other French learned societies. (3) Did this radical experimentalism bring out a transformation of Cartesianism? I establish that, while the first criticism to Descartes concerns his dogmatic pretentions, there emerges in the last 30 years of the seventeenth century what has since become a historiographic cliché, the idea that Cartesians neglected experiments in favor of hypotheses and speculation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Chap. 1 by Dobre and Nyden on the history of this issue.

  2. 2.

    Roux 2012, 2013.

  3. 3.

    For a study of a polemic among Cartesians, see Moreau 1999. For a study of a controversy between proponents and opponents of Cartesianism, see Roux 2012. In the present chapter, I’ll return to a point briefly touched on in this article, that is the way in which the Cartesians appear opposed to experimentalism in this controversy, see Roux 2012, 84–87. The present chapter uses some of the ideas present here and there in Roux 1998.

  4. 4.

    Azouvi 2002.

  5. 5.

    For some comments on the refusal of empiricism among most Cartesians, see Clarke 1989, 43–70. There were however some exceptions, for example Dom Robert Desgabets, Henricus Regius or Pierre-Sylvain Régis. On Desgabets and Régis, see Schmaltz 2002; on Régis see Chap. 6 by Joly; on Regius, see Chap. 7 by Bellis; on Desgabets, see Chap. 8 by Easton.

  6. 6.

    Already at the end of the seventeenth century, Rohault was the Cartesian who could be saved as an experimenter and experimentalist; in this regard see Leibniz to Nicaise published in Journal des savants cited below n132. See also Savérien 1783, xxviii–xxx, lv–lvi; Mouy 1934; Blay, “Introduction,” in Rohault 2009, xxix; Chap. 9 by Dobre in this volume. Clarke 1989, 202–211, proposes a more nuanced, and in my opinion more exact, discussion, if only because coming from a systematic comparison of Malebranche and Rohault, he gives a relative appreciation of Rohault’s experimentalism. The different articles by Trevor McClaughlin devoted to Rohault (in particular McClaughlin 1977, 1996, 2000) must be read, but aside from the fact that they repeat themselves, they do not in my opinion go into enough details of the texts.

  7. 7.

    See for example Koyré 1953; Kuhn 1976; Shapin and Schaffer 1985; Dear 1995.

  8. 8.

    Regulae ad directionem ingenii, Regula V, AT X 380. References to Bacon are to be found in Descartes to Mersenne, January 1630, December 23, 1630, May 10, 1632, AT I 109, 195–196, 251.

  9. 9.

    Discours de la méthode, Cinquième Partie, AT VI 46–55. For comments, see Des Chene 2001, 19–25.

  10. 10.

    Météores, Discours Huitième, AT VI 325–344. For comments, see Garber 2001a, 94–104; Zittel 2009, 202–206, passim.

  11. 11.

    Météores, Discours Sixième, AT VI 298–308. For comments, see Zittel 2009, 219–225. For the idea that such reports are typical for the Royal Society, see Shapin and Schaffer 1985, 60–65; Dear 1995, passim.

  12. 12.

    These two projects, published in AT XI 659–660 and 663–665, were known to Baillet 1691, II, 433–434 and 663–665.

  13. 13.

    Descartes to Mersenne, December 13, 1647, AT V 99.

  14. 14.

    On this point, see Garber 2001b, who holds that this is true for all natural philosophers prior to the Royal Society.

  15. 15.

    I developed this point in Roux 2011, 178–180.

  16. 16.

    The bibliography is large but useless, because it is very repetitive. The discussions that are the most reliable, because they are more nuanced, although not exactly in the same way, seem to me those of Clarke 1982 and Garber 2001a. Homage must also be paid to the studies “Descartes expérimentateur” and “Descartes et Bacon” published in Milhaud 1921.

  17. 17.

    Discours de la méthode, Discours Sixième, AT VI 64–65; Principia philosophiae II 204, AT VIII 327.

  18. 18.

    Rohault 1987, The Author Preface, I, unpaginated.

  19. 19.

    Rohault 1987, The Author Preface, I, unpaginated; 1681, Préface, unpaginated. The verb “prévenir” used transitively did not have the same meaning in the seventeenth century as it does today: “prévenir,” according to Furetière’s Dictionnaire, is “to be the first to do the same thing, to win in races; celui qui prévient arrives the first at the goal, wins the prize.”

  20. 20.

    See for example McClaughlin 2000, 336n52. In the following paragraph, I detail the comments presented in Roux 2011, 128–134.

  21. 21.

    Rohault 1987, I, Chap. XII, 56–78.

  22. 22.

    McClaughlin 1977, 227–228; 1996, 471–475, 480–481 identify the various sources of Rohault’s experiments. We sometimes read that Rohault helped Florin Périer edit Pascal 1663, but I don’t see an argument for this. Nonetheless, the two remarks that make up the Avertissement, unpaginated, of this edition show that the editor knew the work of Rohault; likewise the presentation entitled Nouvelles expériences faites en Angleterre, expliquées par les principes establis dans les deux Traitez precedens de l’Equilibre des Liqueurs, & de la Pesanteur de la masse de l’Air, shows that he knew the work of Boyle.

  23. 23.

    Rohault 1987, I, Chap. XII, Sect. 5, 57; 1681, I, 80 for the French.

  24. 24.

    Rohault 1987, I, Chap. XII, Sect. 6–9, 57–58. This very chapter is analysed in this volume by Mihnea Dobre as well, albeit with quite different conclusions. See Chap. 9 by Dobre.

  25. 25.

    See the texts whose references are given above, n17.

  26. 26.

    Rohault 1987, I, Chap. XII, Sect. 10, 59. Rohault does mention what happens in the case of mercury in Sect. 23, 64, but absolutely not as a crucial experiment.

  27. 27.

    On the use by Clerselier of the affirmation that the reasonings of Rohault anticipate (“préviennent”) experiments, and the way that Rochon mocks this affirmation, see below in the third part of this chapter.

  28. 28.

    Pace McClaughlin 1996, 478.

  29. 29.

    Rohault 1681, I, Chap. XI, Sect. 5, 71.

  30. 30.

    Rohault 1681, I, Chap. IX, Sect. 9–12, 56–60 and Chap. XXI, Sect. 2–3, 160–161. On the addition of these empirical facts, see Roux 2006, 127, where I note that in the preface, Rohault considers this question as too metaphysical.

  31. 31.

    Rohault 1987, I, Chap. V, Sect. 12–13, 34–35; Chap. VII, Sect. 9, 41; Chap. VIII, Sect. 2, 45–46; Chap. IX, Sect. 2, 51 and Sect. 12, 60.

  32. 32.

    Descartes to Vatier, February 22, 1638, AT I 560.

  33. 33.

    Clerselier 1682, unpaginated.

  34. 34.

    McClaughlin 1996, 475–476.

  35. 35.

    McClaughlin 1996, 478, 2000, 341–342.

  36. 36.

    Cassini 1693, 26; Duhamel 1698, 7–9; Fontenelle 1733, 4–5. See on the contrary, and correctly, Brown 1934, 91–105.

  37. 37.

    Brown 1934 is the pioneering work, on which all others rely. See also Mesnard 1963; Taton 1966; Hahn 1971; Hirschfield 1981. For a pertinent critique of the manner in which relations between learned societies and the Académie des sciences were conceived, see Mazauric 2007.

  38. 38.

    Huygens 1888–1950, XXII, 535, 540, 543–544, 554; Borch 1983, III, 423, 435; IV, 173. On Petit and Auzout, see below, n75.

  39. 39.

    Pintard 1951; Béguin 1999, 362–379.

  40. 40.

    Brown 1934, 68–74, discusses the informal meetings that took place at Montmor’s house before 1657. The meetings were interrupted by Roberval’s insult to Montmor, then by political affairs between December 1658 and August 1659 (Boulliau to Huygens, December 6, 1658 and Chapelain to Huygens, August 20, 1659, in Huygens 1888–1950, II, 287, 468; Oldenburg to Saporta, July 11, 1659, in Oldenburg 1965–1973, I, 294–295), then from May to October 1661 because of the illness of Madame de Montmor (Chapelain to Huet, September 26, 1661 and Chapelain to Huygens, October 16, 1661, in Chapelain 1880–1883, II, 153, 159). On the end of Montmor Académy see below, n70.

  41. 41.

    Baillet 1691, II, 442, 462; Bougerel 1737, 372–373, 434–436; Sorbière to Montmor, August 22, 1657, in Sorbière 1660, 371; Chapelain to Heinsius, September 22, 1667, to Bernier, February 16 and April 26, 1669, in Chapelain 1880–1883, II, 530, 622, 640; Chapelain 1662, 52; Denis 1668, 2–3.

  42. 42.

    Sorbière and Du Prat 1657, 634, Art. VII–IX.

  43. 43.

    Sorbière and Du Prat 1657, 633, Art. II–VI. In his letter to Hobbes dated 1 February 1658, in Sorbière 1660, 632, Sorbière indicates that this scheme drew the opposition from those who did not want to have to write speeches.

  44. 44.

    Sorbière and Du Prat 1657, 633, Art. I.

  45. 45.

    Oldenburg to Saporta, July 11, 1659, in Oldenburg 1965–1973, I, 294–295. The question of knowing if the Earth is alive was dealt with by Chapelain, see BNF, Ms. 12847, mentioned in Collas 1912, 331.

  46. 46.

    Sorbière 1660, 60–64, 181–189, 190–193, 194–202, 694–700, 701–704, 712–714.

  47. 47.

    Sorbière 1660, 695, 100.

  48. 48.

    Richard Jones to Boyle, March 20, 1660, in Boyle 2001, I, 405–406.

  49. 49.

    Chapelain to Huygens, May 10, 1658, in Huygens 1888–1950, II, 173–176. Clerselier 1667, unpaginated. Clerselier to Fermat, May 13, 1662, in Descartes 1667, 284–286, passim.

  50. 50.

    Denis 1668, 2–3.

  51. 51.

    Denis 1668, 161.

  52. 52.

    Denis 1668, 216–217.

  53. 53.

    One of the experiments of Pecquet is reported in Oldenburg’s letter to Saporta, August 27, 1659, in Oldenburg 1965–1973, I, 308: “Only Monsr Pecquet brought an experience of his of the winds engendered in the body of man wch was odde, vid. yt he had known a man, who, wherewoever he touched him on his body, gave from him much wind by his mouth, even when he touched him on his tigh or his feeth,” but about Pecquet’s dissections, see especially Sorbière 1660, 22–59. We find the Discours sur l’ascension de l’eau sur un niveau, en un tuyau étroit, récité par Mr. de Montconys, chez Mr. de Montmor in Montconys 1665–1666, III. Thévenot’s spirit level is mentioned in Thévenot 1681, 10–12 and in Thévenot to Huygens, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 18–19.

  54. 54.

    Sorbière 1663, 160.

  55. 55.

    Sorbière 1663, 162.

  56. 56.

    Sorbière 1663, 160, 216.

  57. 57.

    Oldenburg to Michaelis, April 26, 1659, to Hartlib, July 30, 1659, and to Boyle, July 23, 1659, in Oldenburg 1965–1973, I, resp. 240, 260, 287.

  58. 58.

    Boulliau to Huygens, July 11, 1661, in Huygens 1888–1950, III, 293.

  59. 59.

    Huygens 1888–1950, XXII, 535, 537, 539, 540, 543, 544, 546, 553, 554, 560.

  60. 60.

    Denis 1668, 2–3.

  61. 61.

    McClaughlin 1975. It cannot be contested that this project prefigures more the Académie des sciences than do the notes that, probably at the request of Colbert, were written in 1666 by Jean Chapelain and Charles Perrault, both members of the “Petite Académie,” a small council in charge of proposing initiatives to glorify the King (Perrault 1666). The main goal of Chapelain’s note, published in Chapelain 1666, 513 (Collas 1912, 384–388, establishes that Chapelain was the author) was to distinguish “scientists by profession,” who are busy only with cabals in the court, and “good faith scientists,” who of course were the true scientists. The note from Charles Perrault, who proposed an “Académie Royale générale” divided into four sections (Belles-Lettres, History, Philosophy, in the sense of natural philosophy, Mathematics), is very short and the project it promotes was soon abandoned because it faced resistance from already established institutions as the Sorbonne and the Académie française (Duhamel 1698, 7–9; Fontenelle 1733, 5–7).

  62. 62.

    Sorbière 1663, 160–161.

  63. 63.

    Sorbière 1663, 161.

  64. 64.

    Huygens, Journal, November 9, 1660, in Huygens 1888–1950, XXII, 535; Christiaan Huygens to Lodewijk Huygens, April 26, 1662, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 117.

  65. 65.

    Chapelain to Heinsius, February 6, 1659, in Chapelain 1880–1883, II, 17.

  66. 66.

    Boulliau to Heinsius, February 1658, quoted and translated in Brown 1934, 78–79.

  67. 67.

    On this point, begin with Brown 1934, 119–122.

  68. 68.

    Chapelain to Huygens, May 30, 1661, in Huygens 1888–1950, III, 273.

  69. 69.

    Huygens to Chapelain, July 14, and Chapelain to Huygens, July 20, 1661, in Huygens 1888–1950, III, 295 and 299.

  70. 70.

    Huygens to Moray, June 12, 1664, Huygens 1888–1950, V, 70. Chapelain to Bernier, February 16, 1669, in Chapelain 1880–1883, II, 622.

  71. 71.

    McClaughlin 1974. The most detailed study of the various activities of Thévenot is currently that of Dew 2009, 81–130.

  72. 72.

    Thévenot 1694, Avertissement, unpaginated.

  73. 73.

    Thévenot 1681, 8.

  74. 74.

    It is in this edition that it is said that these two speeches were made at the Académie Montmor before being published, without their authors being named.

  75. 75.

    Petit to Huygens, March 8 and May 5, 1662, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 73, 127. From the beginning of his correspondence with Huygens, Petit complained of the way in which, in France, people of quality neglected mechanics, see Petit to Huygens, in Huygens 1888–1950, II, 257. Petit, Auzout and Thévenot are mentioned meeting on Tuesdays in the letter from Petit to Huygens, 17 October 1664, in Huygens 1888–1950, V, 124. The same three would meet Christopher Wren when he came to Paris a few years later (Oldenburg to Boyle, August 24, 1665, in Oldenburg 1965–1973, II, 480). Pierre Petit (1598–1682), born in Montluçon, resided in Paris from 1633 on, wrote objections against the metaphysics of the Discourse on Method and against the explanation of refractions in the Dioptrique, and communicated Torricelli’s experiment to Pascal. Intendant général des fortifications from 1649, he was part of the various scientific circles and regretted not being a member of the Académie des sciences (see the lettre from Boulliau quoted by Brown 1934, 138). The explanation can perhaps be found in his character; see the cruel portrait made of him in Sorbière to Hobbes, early 1663, in Hobbes 1994, 551–554; and Christiaan Huygens to Lodewijk Huygens, September 28 and November 9, 1662, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 241, 256, passim. Adrien Auzout (1620–1691), born in Rouen, contributed to Pascal’s experiments on the vacuum, worked as an astronomer with Jean Picard at the Académie des sciences, of which he was briefly a member (1666–1668) before retiring to Italy and England, apparently for having criticized Charles Perrault’s translation of Vitruvius; see Brown 1934, 138, 138–141.

  76. 76.

    Sorbière to Hobbes, December 23, 1662, in Hobbes 1994, 542. Petit to Huygens, November 8, 1662, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 262, mentions also that the Académie Montmor was on the verge of moving to the home of Sourdis.

  77. 77.

    Christiaan Huygens to Lodewijk Huygens, April 6, 1663, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 324–325. Christiaan Huygens to [Constantyn Huygens], April 20 and May 4, 1663, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 333, 338. Contrary to what the editors of Huygens’s Œuvres complètes affirm, the d’Espagnet who appears in Huygens correspondence may not be the chemist Jean d’Espagnet (1564–1637?), first Président of the Parlement of Bordeaux: it is more likely his son, Étienne d’Espagnet, counselor at the Parlement of Bordeaux.

  78. 78.

    Huygens to Moray, November 18 and December 19, 1663, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 433, 474. Huygens to Constantyn Huygens, November 30, 1663, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 452. Auzout to Christiaan Huygens, December 1663, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 481–482. The unreliability of the Montmor pump was noted by Shapin and Schaffer 1985, 265–269.

  79. 79.

    Huygens to Moray, March 12, 1664, in Huygens 1888–1950, V, 41.

  80. 80.

    Borch 1983, III, 464; IV, 6–7, 164, 173, 180–181, 186, 274, 283–284. Borch attributes the anatomical observations to Swammerdam, it is Chapelain to Huet, July 31, 1665, in Chapelain 1880–1883, II, 406, who mentions Steno. This anatomical fashion was in no way proper to the meetings of Thévenot: Borch mentions the anatomical preparations that took place at the home of Montmor in February 1665 (when the Académie was no longer meeting there) and the ones done by Steno at the home of Bourdelot in May 1665.

  81. 81.

    Chapelain to Steno, March 15, 1666 and May 27, 1667, in Chapelain 1880–1883, II, 447, 514.

  82. 82.

    Borch also mentions, among those regularly meeting at the home of Thévenot, Vossius (the scholar Isaac Vossius, 1618–1689), Borelli (the chemist and builder of instruments Jacques Borelly (?–1689), later a member of the Académie des sciences), Ville Bressé, Bressié or Bressieu (the chemist and engineer Étienne de Villebressieu, who travelled with Descartes at the beginning of the 1630s, and who was the most important source for his first biographer, Pierre Borel, for this period), Frenicle (the mathematician Bernard Frenicle de Bessy (?–1674), who was already living in the home of Thévenot), and Martell (Thomas de Martel (1618–1619–1679–1685?), a bourgeois of Montauban, who was already part of the scientific circles of Paris at the beginning of the 1640s, was a correspondent of Hobbes, then of Oldenburg; the best biography to date is that of Noel Malcolm in his edition of Hobbes’ Correspondence).

  83. 83.

    Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 325–329.

  84. 84.

    McClaughlin 1975, 236; see also Dew 2009, 96. The autobiography of Thévenot found in the Avertissement of Thévenot 1694 affirms that this project was presented to Colbert.

  85. 85.

    Thévenot 1681, 3–6.

  86. 86.

    See for example Bacon, Novum organum, I, 73–74, in Bacon 1996–, XI, 116–119.

  87. 87.

    Descartes to Plempius for Fromondus, October 3, 1637, AT I 421.

  88. 88.

    Thévenot 1681, 7.

  89. 89.

    This point is already highlighted in McClaughlin 1975, 238–242, who notes the common points between the project for the Compagnie des sciences et des arts and the practices of the Académie des sciences, which is true, but who also suggests that this commonality of doctrine arises from a Gassendist reference, which seems doubtful to me.

  90. 90.

    Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 329.

  91. 91.

    Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 327. The first reception of Bacon in France was explored in Le Dœuff 1984; on baconianism in mathematics, see Goldstein 2008. The question of the reference to Bacon in late seventeenth century France remains however to be explored, but it may be noted that it was Huygens who in December 1660 lent Thévenot Bacon’s Opuscula varia posthuma, philosophica, civilia, et theologica, published 2 years prior, and that one finds in his later projects for the assembly of physics in an injunction to “work on natural history more or less following the plan of Verulamius” (Huygens 1888–1950, XXII, 540; VI, 95–96 and XIX, 268).

  92. 92.

    Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 325–327.

  93. 93.

    The most exhaustive presentation of Rohault’s Mercredis remains that of Clair 1978, 42–56.

  94. 94.

    Clerselier 1659, unpaginated.

  95. 95.

    Clair 1978, 43.

  96. 96.

    Fontenelle 1994, 143.

  97. 97.

    Moreri 1759, 310. Clerselier 1657, unpaginated. Le Bret 1657 (unpaginated) is all the more telling that, regarding Cyrano’s illness, he explicitly mentions Rohault, and does not mention the Mercredis: “I would do ill to Monsieur Rohault if I didn’t add his name to such a glorious list, since this illustrious mathematician who carried out so many beautiful physical proofs…had so great a friendship for Monsieur de Bergerac…that he was the first to discover the true cause of his illness….”

  98. 98.

    Baillet 1691, II, 442.

  99. 99.

    Clerselier 1659, unpaginated.

  100. 100.

    About this battle, see Roux 2012. See also Chap. 2 by Ariew.

  101. 101.

    Clerselier 1682, unpaginated.

  102. 102.

    Clair 1978, 46–49.

  103. 103.

    Clerselier 1682, unpaginated.

  104. 104.

    Rohault 1660. McClaughlin 1977, 228n18, attributes this manuscript to René Fédé. Clair 1978, 50–56, provides a few extracts.

  105. 105.

    Quoted in Clair 1978, 46.

  106. 106.

    Huygens 1888–1950, XXII, 541.

  107. 107.

    On the criticism that Hobbes addressed to the Royal Society as a closed private space, see Shapin and Schaffer, 1985, 113–114.

  108. 108.

    Huygens 1888–1950, XXII, 536; Borch 1983, III, 423.

  109. 109.

    Clerselier 1682, unpaginated. I highlight.

  110. 110.

    See for example Rohault 1660, 1r: “…the conferences were written in a tumult, and at odd hours, he [the person collecting the conferences] was not as able as he would have liked to imitate the correctness and the incomparable precision of the terms of he who had the task of representing the feelings.” Foucher 1675, 64–65: “You know that he was intent on reasoning with consequence, and as he perfectly possessed all the subjects he dealt with, he explained them with a great deal of order, and with a certain clarity, accompanied by a natural eloquence that one recognized more in its effect than in the disposition of the terms he would use.” Malebranche, Recherche de la vérité, Preface to Volume II, in Malebranche 1958–1967, II, 564: “…everyone know with what accuracy and what force this learned man resisted the blows that others wanted to bear to him, and that with two or three words pronounced without heat and without movement, he struck down the imagination of those full of themselves who thought to cover him in embarrassment.” Clerselier 1682, unpaginated: “… he summarized so well and in such good order everything objected to him, and responded with such clarity and enlightenment.…”.

  111. 111.

    Clerselier 1682, unpaginated. On the meaning of the verb “prévenir,” see above, n19. Three pages later, he refers again to the magnet, where the experiments had been anticipated (“prévenues”) by the speeches.

  112. 112.

    Clerselier 1682, unpaginated; Huygens 1888–1950, XXII, 539, 540.

  113. 113.

    Rohault 1660, 12r.

  114. 114.

    Huygens 1888–1950, XXII, 536, 541; III, 210. One can note in passing that although at times one speaks of the “emancipatory” character of Cartesianism for women, the attitude of Huygens and his correspondents to this senatulus should lead one to a more nuanced judgment as to the type of knowledge women could access in this period; and it is significant that there is no sign of the presence of women in the most visible learned societies, whether the Académie Montmor, the Académie Bourdelot, or the Compagnie des sciences et des arts.

  115. 115.

    Huygens 1888–1950, III, 397, 414, 432; IV, 6, 7, 11, 69, 367, 459; V, 29, 41, 101, 105. Aside from correspondence, Rohault’s Traité de physique is mentioned in the preface of the Discours de la cause de la pesanteur; it also appears in certain critical notes on the Cartesian explanation of magnetism (Huygens 1888–1950, XIX, 572).

  116. 116.

    On Rohault’s description and explanation of these phenomena, see Rohault 1681, I, Chap. XXII, Sect. 67–84, 204–214. On Huygens’ lack of confidence in Rohault’s explanation, see his letters to Moray from December 9, 1663, February 20 and March 12, 1664, resp. in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 459; V, 29, 41.

  117. 117.

    Christiaan Huygens to Lodewijk Huygens, January 18, 1662, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 11. See as well the letter to the same from January 4, in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 6–7.

  118. 118.

    Garber 1988.

  119. 119.

    In his letter to Francheville, March 16, 1665, in Chapelain 1880–1883, II, 390, Chapelain accuses Sorbière of having copied Gassendi without understanding him.

  120. 120.

    On Chapelain’s Gassendism, see Collas 1912, 60–64, 151–154, 331–336, 383–388. On Sorbière’s Gassendism, see Pintard 1983, 334–348, nuanced however 418–420, 425, 429. On the responsibility of the Gassendists on the fact that the first members of the Académie des sciences were not Cartesians, see Taton 1966, 36; on the fact that they would have been ipso facto Gassendists and experimentalists, see McClaughlin 1975, 239–240.

  121. 121.

    See in particular Chapelain to Balzac, May 31 and December 29, 1637, in Chapelain 1880–1883, I, 153, 189; Sorbière to Petit, February 10, 1657, in Sorbière 1660, 691. On the fact that the illustrations and comparisons used by Descartes would calm the crowd, see Sorbière to Mersenne, December 23, 1647, in Mersenne 1932–1988, XV, 585–587. On Gassendi’s “too great literature,” see Sorbière 1694, 124–126.

  122. 122.

    On the experimental practice of Gassendi, see Rochot 1964; as for his judgment on Cartesian physics, he responds to Rivet who asked him for a critique (censura) of the Principia philosophiae that it was superfluous, for such a work should die before its author, see Gassendi 1964, VI, 217.

  123. 123.

    Sorbière to Petit, November 10 and February 10, 1657, in Sorbière 1660, 679 and 691. Conversely, Clerselier 1667 notes that Roberval refused to put in writing his objections to Descartes.

  124. 124.

    Sorbière to Petit, November 10, 1657, in Sorbière 1660, 679–680. For other passages where Descartes is described as a “head of a sect,” see Sorbière to Saumaise, March 10, 1650 and to Petit, February 10, 1657, in Sorbière 1660, 535, 691. In the correspondence to Mersenne, Descartes is compared to Fludd, see Sorbière to Mersenne, April 15 and December 23, 1647, in Mersenne 1932–1988, XV, 201, 585–587.

  125. 125.

    Chapelain to Carrel de Sainte-Garde, May 27, 1662, in Chapelain 1880–1883, II, 235–236. The word “sectators” describes Cartesians in Chapelain to Heinsius, February 6, 1659, to Carrel de Sainte-Garde, December 15, 1663 and to Bernier, February 16 and April 26, 1669, in Chapelain 1880–1883, 17, 341, 622, 640.

  126. 126.

    Sorbière to Saumaise, March 10, 1650, in Sorbière 1660, 536.

  127. 127.

    Chapelain to Carrel de Sainte-Garde, February 16, 1662, in Chapelain 1880–1883, II, 203–204. Carrel de Sainte Garde published in 1663 his Lettres contre la philosophie de Descartes.

  128. 128.

    Huygens 1888–1950, X, 404–405.

  129. 129.

    Huygens to Meier, June 1691, in Huygens 1888–1950, X, 104. See also to Meier, March 26, 1691, in Huygens 1888–1950, X, 54.

  130. 130.

    Leibniz to Huygens, February 20, 1691, in Huygens 1888–1950, X, 52. The notes of Leibniz on Baillet can be found in Leibniz 1961, IV, 315–324.

  131. 131.

    Leibniz to Pelisson, March 18, 1692, in Leibniz 1923–, I–7, 292.

  132. 132.

    Journal des scavants, April 13, 1693, 163–164. On the fact that Cartesians did not discover anything, see Leibniz to Gallois, [1677] and to Malebranche, June 22, 1679 in Leibniz 1923–, II–1, 569, 717; to Swelingius, in Leibniz 1961, IV, 329–330.

  133. 133.

    Roux 2011.

  134. 134.

    Mariotte 1992, 97, 103.

  135. 135.

    Mariotte 1992, 98.

  136. 136.

    Mariotte 1717, I, 170–171; II, 341.

  137. 137.

    Mariotte 1992, 98.

  138. 138.

    Brockliss 1995a, 454–456; 1995b, 190–194, 199, 209–216.

  139. 139.

    Rochon 1673, Sect. 47, 120–122.

  140. 140.

    Rochon 1673, Sect. 48, 122–124.

  141. 141.

    Rochon 1673, Sect. 50, 128–129.

  142. 142.

    Rochon 1673, Sects. 59–60, 140–144, and 142 for the quotation.

  143. 143.

    Rochon 1673, Sect. 84, 194–196.

  144. 144.

    Rochon 1673, Sect. 85, 197–198. “Prévenir l’expérience” is what Rohault claimed to do with his third sort of experiment, see above.

  145. 145.

    Rochon 1673, Sect. 85, 202.

  146. 146.

    Voltaire to Maupertuis, October 1, 1738, in Voltaire 1968–1977, V, 307–308: “if one had to get into this other and no less frivolous question, which one nonetheless agitates, of knowing who was the greater physicist, Descartes or Newton, it would be enough to consider that Descartes almost never carried out experiments…. If one wanted to discuss the physics of Descartes, what could one perceive there other than hypotheses?”

  147. 147.

    AT XI 31, 48.

  148. 148.

    See the references given in Roux 2006, n40.

References

  • Azouvi, François. 2002. Descartes et la France. Histoire d’une passion nationale. Paris: Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, Francis. 1996. The Oxford Francis Bacon, 15 vols, ed. G. Rees and L. Jardine. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillet, Adrien. 1691. La vie de M. Descartes, 2 vols. Paris: Daniel Horthemels.

    Google Scholar 

  • Béguin, Katia. 1999. Les Princes de Condé. Rebelles, courtisans et mécènes dans la France du Grand Siècle. Seyssel: Champ Vallon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borch, Ole. 1983. The Journal of the Danish polyhistor Ole Borch, ed. with introduction and indices by H.D. Schepelern, 4 vols. Copenhagen/London: Reitzels Forlag, Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bougerel, Joseph. 1737. Vie de Pierre Gassendi. Paris: Jacques Vincent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, Robert. 2001. The correspondence of Robert Boyle, ed. Michael Hunter, Antonio Clericuzio, and Lawrence M. Principe. London: Pickering & Chatto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brockliss, Laurence W.B. 1995a. Descartes, Gassendi, and the Reception of the Mechanical Philosophy at the French Collèges de Plein Exercice, 1640–1730. Perspectives on Science 3(4): 450–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brockliss, Laurence W.B. 1995b. Pierre Gautruche et l’enseignement de la philosophie de la nature dans les collèges jésuites français vers 1650. In Les Jésuites à la Renaissance, ed. Luce Giard, 187–219. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Harcourt. 1934. Scientific organizations in seventeenth century France. New York: Russel and Russel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassini, Giovanni Domenico. 1693. De l’origine et du progrès de l’Astronomie, et de son usage dans la Geographie et la Navigation. In Recueil d’observations faits en plusieurs voyages par ordre de sa Majesté… par Messieurs de l’Académie Royale des sciences. Paris: Imprimerie Royale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chapelain, Jean. 1662. Liste de quelques gens de lettres vivans en 1662. Composée par ordre de M. Colbert, par M. Chapelain. In Memoires de littérature et d’histoire. Tome second, ed. P. Desmolets. Paris: Noyons, 1749.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chapelain, Jean. 1666. Lettre de M. Chapelain à M. Colbert dans lesquelles il expose son sentiment sur les divers projets de création et d’encouragement que méditait le ministre en faveur des arts et des sciences. In Lettres, instructions et mémoires de Colbert, vol. V, ed. Pierre Clément, 513–514, 8 vols. Paris: Perrin, 1861–1882.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chapelain, Jean. 1880–1883. Lettres de Jean Chapelain, ed. Philippe Tamizey de Larroque, 2 vols. Paris: Imprimerie Nationale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clair, Pierre. 1978. Jacques Rohault (1618–1672). Bio-bibliographie. Avec l’édition critique des Entretiens sur la philosophie. Paris: CNRS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, Desmond M. 1982. Descartes’ philosophy of science. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, Desmond M. 1989. Occult powers and hypotheses. Cartesian natural philosophy under Louis XIV. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clerselier, Claude. 1657. Préface. In Descartes, Lettres de Monsieur Descartes. Tome Premier, ed. Claude Clerselier. Paris: Charles Angot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clerselier, Claude. 1659. Préface. In Lettres de Monsieur Descartes. Tome second, ed. Claude Clerselier. Paris: Charles Angot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clerselier, Claude. 1667. Préface. In Lettres de Monsieur Descartes. Tome troisième et dernier, ed. Claude Clerselier. Paris: Charles Angot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clerselier, Claude. 1682. Préface. In Œuvres posthumes de Rohault, ed. Claude Clerselier. Paris: Guillaume Desprez.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collas, Georges. 1912. Jean Chapelain. 1595–1574. Étude historique et littéraire d’après des documents inédits. Paris: Perrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dear, Peter. 1995. Discipline and experience. The mathematical way in the scientific revolution. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Denis, Jean-Baptiste. 1668. Lettre écrite à Monsieur Sorbière… par Jean Denis, touchant l’origine de la transfusion du sang et la manière de la pratiquer sur les hommes. Paris: Jean Cusson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Des Chene, Dennis. 2001. Spirits and clocks. Machine and organism in Descartes. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, René. 1667. Lettres de Monsieur Descartes. Tome troisième et dernier, ed. Claude Clerselier. Paris: Charles Angot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dew, Nicholas. 2009. Orientalism in Louis XIV’s France. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Duhamel, Jean-Baptiste. 1698. Regiae scientiarum Academiae historia. Paris: Jean-Baptiste Delespine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fontenelle, Bernard Le Bovier de. 1733. Histoire de l’Académie royale des Sciences. Tome I. Depuis son établissement jusqu’à 1686. Paris: Gabriel Martin, Jean-Baptiste Coignard et Hyppolite-Louis Guérin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fontenelle, Bernard Le Bovier de. 1994. Œuvres complètes. Tome VI. Paris: Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucher, Simon. 1675. Critique de la recherche de la vérité. Où l’on examine en même temps une partie des principes de Mr Descartes. Lettre par un académicien. Paris: Martin Coustelier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel. 1988. Descartes, the Aristotelians, and the revolution that did not happen in 1637. The Monist 71(4): 471–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel. 2001a. Descartes and experiment in the Discourse and Essays. In Descartes embodied. Reading Cartesian philosophy through Cartesian science, 85–110. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel. 2001b. Experiment, community, and the constitution of nature in the seventeenth century. In Descartes embodied. Reading Cartesian philosophy through Cartesian science, 296–328. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gassendi, Pierre. 1658. Opera Omnia, Lyon, 6 vols. Repr. Stuttgart: Friedrich Fromman Verlag, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gassendi, Pierre. 1964. Opera Omnia, 6 vols. Lyon 1658. Repr. Stuttgart: Friedrich Fromman Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, Catherine. 2008. Écrire l’expérience mathématique au XVIIe siècle; la méthode selon Bernard Frenicle de Bessy. In Réduire en art. La technologie de la Renaissance aux Lumières, ed. Pascal Dubourg-Glattigny and Hélène Vérin, 213–224. Paris: Éditions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, Roger. 1971. The Anatomy of a Scientific Institution. The Paris Academy of Sciences, 1666–1803. Berkeley/Los Angeles/London: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschfield, John Milton. 1981. The Académie royale des sciences. 1666–1683. New York: Arno Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1994. Thomas Hobbes. The correspondence: 1660–1679, The Clarendon edition of the works of Thomas Hobbes, vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huygens, Christiaan. 1888–1950. Œuvres complètes de Christian Huygens, 22 vols, ed. Société Hollandaise des Sciences. La Haye: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré, Alexandre. 1953. An experiment in measurement. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 97(2): 222–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas. 1976. Tradition mathématique et tradition expérimentale dans l’évolution des sciences physiques. Journal of Interdisciplinary History 7: 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Bret, Henri. 1657. Préface. In Histoire comique par Monsieur de Cyrano Bergerac. Contenant les Estats & Empires de la Lune, ed. Henri Le Bret. Paris: Charles de Sercy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Dœuff, Michèle. 1984. Bacon chez les Grands au siècle de Louis XIII. In Francis Bacon. Terminologia e fortuna nel XVII secolo, ed. Marta Fattori, 155–178. Roma: Ateneo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1923–. Leibniz. Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe, Preussische (then Deutsche) Akademie der Wissenschaften ed. Darmstadt, then Leipzig, then Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1961. Die philosophischen Schriften von G. W. Leibniz (1875–1890), 7 vols. Repr., ed. C.I. Gerhardt. Hildesheim/New York: G. Olms.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malebranche, Nicolas. 1958–1967. Œuvres de Malebranche, 20 vols., ed. André Robinet. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mariotte, Edme. 1717. Œuvres de Mr Mariotte, de l’Académie Royale des Sciences, divisées en deux tomes, Comprenant tous les Traitez de cet Auteur, tant ceux qui avoient déjà paru séparément, que ceux qui n’avoient pas encore été publiez. Leiden: P. van der Aa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mariotte, Edme. 1992. Essai de logique, ed. Alan Gabbey and Guy Picolet. Paris: Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazauric, Simone. 2007. Fontenelle et l’invention de l’histoire des sciences à l’aube des Lumières. Paris: Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClaughlin, Trevor. 1974. Une lettre de Melchisédec Thévenot. Revue d’histoire des sciences 27(2): 123–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClaughlin, Trevor. 1975. Sur les rapports entre la Compagnie de Thévenot et l’Académie royale des Sciences. Revue d’histoire des sciences 28(3): 235–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClaughlin, Trevor. 1977. Le concept de science chez Jacques Rohault. Revue d’histoire des sciences 30(3): 225–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClaughlin, Trevor. 1996. Was there an empirical movement in mid-seventeenth century France? Experiments in Jacques Rohault’s Traité de physique. Revue d’histoire des sciences 49(4): 459–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClaughlin, Trevor. 2000. Descartes, experiments, and a first generation Cartesian, Jacques Rohault. In Descartes’ natural philosophy, ed. Stephan Gaukroger, John Schuster, and John Sutton, 330–345. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mersenne, Marin. 1932–1988. Correspondance du P. Marin Mersenne, religieux minime, Paul Tannery, Cornélis de Waard and Armand Beaulieu eds., 17 vols. Paris: Éditions du CNRS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mesnard, Jean. 1963. Pascal à l’Académie Le Pailleur. Revue d’histoire des sciences 16(1): 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milhaud, Gaston. 1921. Descartes savant. Paris: Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monconys, Balthazar de. 1665–1666. Journal des voyages de Monsieur de Monconys, 3 vols. Lyon: Horace Boissat & George Remeus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreau, Denis. 1999. Deux cartésiens. La polémique entre Antoine Arnauld et Nicolas Malebranche. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreri, Louis. 1759. Le Grand dictionnaire historique ou Mélange curieux de l’histoire sacrée et profane. Tome Neuvième. Paris: Les Libraires associés.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouy, Paul. 1934. Le développement de la physique cartésienne, 1646–1712. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oldenburg, Henry. 1965–1973. The correspondence of Henry Oldenburg, 9 vols., ed. and trans. Alfred Rupert Hall et Marie Boas Hall. Madison, Wisconsin-London: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pascal, Blaise. 1663. Traitez de l’quilibre des liqueurs et de la pesanteur de la masse de l’air. Paris: Guillaume Desprez.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrault, Charles. 1666. Note de Charles Perrault à Colbert pour l’établissement d’une académie générale. In Lettres, instructions et mémoires de Colbert, vol. V, ed. Pierre Clément, 512–513, 8 vols. Paris: Perrin, 1861–1882.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pintard, René. 1951. Autour de Pascal: l’Académie Bourdelot et la querelle du vide. In Mélanges d’histoires littéraires offerts à Daniel Mornet, 73–81. Paris: Nizet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pintard, René. 1983. Le libertinage érudit dans la première moitié du xviie siècle, 2nd ed. Paris/Genève: Slatkine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rochon, Antoine. 1673. Lettre d’un philosophe à un cartésien de ses amis. Paris: Estienne Michallet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rochot, Bernard. 1964. Gassendi et l’expérience. In Mélanges Alexandre Koyré, vol. II, 411–422. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohault, Jacques. 1660. Conférences, recueillies par M. F. avocat qui y a, dit-il, ajouté du sien. Mss 2225, Bibliothèque Sainte-Geneviève, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohault, Jacques. 1681. Traité de physique, 2 vols. Lyon: Claude Galbit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohault, Jacques. 1987. System of natural philosophy, illustrated with Dr. Samuel Clarke’s notes, taken mostly out of Sir Isaac Newton’s philosophy. New York/London: Garland Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohault, Jacques. 2009. Physique nouvelle (1667), ed. Sylvain Matton. Paris/Milan: Séha, Archè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roux, Sophie. 1998. Le scepticisme et les hypothèses de la physique. Revue de synthèse 119(2–3): 211–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roux, Sophie. 2006. La philosophie naturelle à l’époque de Le Nôtre. Remarques sur la philosophie mécanique et sur le cartésianisme. In Fragments d’un paysage culturel, André Le Nôtre, Institutions, arts, sciences et techniques, ed. Georges Fahrat, 98–111. Sceaux: Musée de l’Île-de-France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roux, Sophie. 2011. L’Essai de logique de Mariotte. Archéologie des idées d’un savant ordinaire. Paris: Classiques Garnier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roux, Sophie. 2012. A French Partition of the Empire of Natural Philosophy (1670–1690). In The mechanisation of natural philosophy, ed. Daniel Garber and Sophie Roux, 55–98. New York/Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roux, Sophie. 2013. Pour une conception polémique du cartésianisme. Ignace-Gaston Pardies et Antoine Dilly dans la querelle de l’âme des bêtes. In Qu’est-ce qu’être cartésien? ed. Delphine Kolesnik, 315–337. Lyon: Presses de l’ENS de Lyon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savérien, Alexandre. 1783. Histoire des philosophes modernes. Tome VI. Histoire des physiciens. Paris: Bleut and Guillaume.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmaltz, Tad. 2002. Radical Cartesianism: the French reception of Descartes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven, and Simon Schaffer. 1985. Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorbière, Samuel. 1660. Lettres et Discours sur diverses matières curieuses. Paris: François Clousier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorbière, Samuel. 1694. Sorberiana sive Excerpta ex ore Samëlis Sorbiere. Toulouse: Colomeis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorbière, Samuel. 1663. Discours prononcé le 3 d’avril 1663. À l’ouverture de l’Académie de physiciens qui s’assemblent tous les mardis chez Monsieur de Montmor. In Guillaume Bigourdan, Les premières réunions savantes de Paris au XVIIe siècle, Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l’Académie des sciences, 164, séances du 22 et du 29 janvier 1917:159–162 and 216–218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorbière, Samuel, and Du Prat, Abraham. 1657. Règlement de l’assemblée de physiciens, qui se fit à Paris, chez Monsieur de Montmor l’an 1657. In Sorbière à Hobbes, 1er fév. 1658, in Sorbière 1660: 633–634. To be found also in Huygens 1888–1950, IV, 514–515.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taton, René. 1966. Les origines de l’Académie royale des sciences, Conférence du Palais de la Découverte, 15 mai 1965. Paris: Palais de la Découverte.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thévenot, Melchisédech. 1681. Discours sur l’art de la navigation. In Recueil de voyages de Mr Thévenot dédiés au Roi. Paris: Estienne Michallet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thévenot, Melchisédech. 1694. Bibliotheca Thevotiana sive Catalogus impressorum et manuscriptorum Liborum Bibliothecae viri Clarissimi D. Melchisedecis Thevenot. Paris: Florentin et Pierre Delaulne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltaire, François-Marie Arouet. 1968–1977. Les Œuvres complètes de Voltaire. Geneva/Banbury/Oxford: Institut et Musée Voltaire & Voltaire Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zittel, Claus. 2009. Theatrum philosophicum. Descartes und die Rolle ästhetischer Formen in der Wissenschaft. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sophie Roux .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Roux, S. (2013). Was There a Cartesian Experimentalism in 1660s France?. In: Dobre, M., Nyden, T. (eds) Cartesian Empiricisms. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 31. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7690-6_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics