Skip to main content

The Formation of Competing Optical Traditions in Early and Late Antiquity

  • Chapter
Historical Roots of Cognitive Science

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 208))

  • 140 Accesses

Abstract

No doubt the greatest medieval scholar in the field of optics was the Arab Ibn al-Haytham (fl. ca. 1000 AD), known in the West, and immensely influential, under the name of Alhazen or Alhacen. Before his time three clearly distinguishable optical traditions existed in the Arab academic world whose theoretical foundations and ideas concerning even such fundamental questions as the very aim of optics were so vastly different that sometimes one gets the impression that they represented altogether different areas of research rather than competing research programs for one and the same domain of phenomena.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Cf. I. Lakatos, History of Science and its Rational Reconstruction’, in P.S.A. 1970, Studies in the Philosophy of Science 8, R.C. Buck and R.S. Cohen (eds.), (Dordrecht, 1971), pp. 91–135.

    Google Scholar 

  2. As A.I. Sabra points out, Alhazen’s basar, like the Greek δψιs (opsis) and the Latin visus means both eye and sight (or sense or faculty of sight). Cf. A.I. Sabra, ‘Sensation and Inference in Alhazen’s Theory of Visual Perception’, in Studies in Perception, P.K. Machamer and R.G. Turnbull (eds.), (Columbus, 1978), p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. below, ch. IV, 3, p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  4. De sensu 6, 446b 12 ff., The Student’s Oxford Aristotle, W.D. Ross (ed.), (New York, 1942), Vol. III. All subsequent references to works by Aristotle are taken from this edition unless otherwise indicated.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. ibid. 2, 437a 18–438b 2. Also cf. De anima 2, 7, 419a 12–21.

    Google Scholar 

  6. De sensu 3, 439a 21–25; De anima 2, 7,418a 29–418b 9.

    Google Scholar 

  7. De anima 2, 7, 418b 9–19.

    Google Scholar 

  8. De sensu 6, 446b 22–447a 17.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., 3,439b 11f.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid., 3,439a 27–34.

    Google Scholar 

  11. De anima 2, 7,419a 8–21.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. De anima, 1, 3, 407a 7; 2, 5, 418a 3–6; 2, 12, 424a 16–24; 3, 1,425b 17; 3, 4, 429a 28; 3, 8, 432a 1.

    Google Scholar 

  13. The radical notion of the fundamental applicability of mathematics to the physical world is a novel idea gradually prepared in the development of medieval optics (as I will argue in ch. V; also cf. ch. III, sec. 4) to be consciously embraced only by the founders of modern science. Its radical content as well as its complicated history militate against its being simply classified among the ancient wisdoms of Plato. At any rate, in a strict sense this notion is not Platonic in origin at all. It is no surprise, therefore, to find intellectual historians recently making a compelling case against the myth of popular historiography according to which Galileo was a Platonist. Galileo certainly did not share Plato’s view of the relationship between the intelligible and the sensible. Cf. Dudley Shapere, Galileo: A Philosophical Study, (Chicago, 1974) and Hans Blumenberg, Tseudoplatonismen in der Naturwissenschaft der frühen Neuzeit’, Akademie der Wissenschaften und der Literatur, Abh. der Geistes- und Sozialwissenschaftlichen Klasse, (Mainz, 1971), nr. 1, pp. 3–34.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cf. R. Descartes, Principles of Philosophy, II, 20 (HR 1264); II, 34 f. (HR 1267).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Claudius Galenus, De placitis Hippocratis et Piatonis, Libri novem, Vol. I, Prolegomena critica, textum graecum, adnotationem criticum versionemque latinam continens, Iwan Mueller (ed.), (Leipzig, 1874), 7, 615, 9–13 (K 5, 618). Subsequent references will be to this edition of Galen’s De placitis, to be followed, in parentheses, by the corresponding reference in the Kühn edition of Galen’s works.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf. S. Sambursky, Physics of the Stoics, (London, 1959), pp. 1–11. On the composition of pneuma, cf. e.g. Alex. Aphr., De anima, 26,16; De Mixt., 224,15.

    Google Scholar 

  17. On the discovery of the nerves and the persistent theory of the hollow nerves, cf. Friedrich Solmsen, ‘Greek Philosophy and the Discovery of the Nerves’, Museum Helveticum 18 (1961) 150–167

    Google Scholar 

  18. On the discovery of the nerves and the persistent theory of the hollow nerves, cf. Friedrich Solmsen, ‘Greek Philosophy and the Discovery of the Nerves’, Museum Helveticum 18 (1961) 169–97

    Google Scholar 

  19. Edwin Clarke, ‘The Doctrine of the Hollow Nerve in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries’, in Medicine, Science, and Culture-Historical Essays in Honor of Owsei Temkin, Lloyd G. Stevenson and Robert P. Multhauf (eds.), (Baltimore, 1968), pp. 123–41.

    Google Scholar 

  20. De placitis 7,615, 3–7 (K 5, 617); 7, 616,14—617,4 (K 5, 619).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., 7, 623, 2–7 (K 5,625).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cf. E J. Dijksterhuis, De mechanisering van het wereldbeeld, (Amsterdam, 1950), p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Cf. T.S. Kuhn, The Essential Tension, (Chicago, 1977), pp. 37–8.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf. T.S. Kuhn, The Essential Tension, (Chicago, 1977), pp. 35 Ibid. p. 35 (emphasis added). Kuhn especially classifies astronomy, harmonics, mathematics, optics and statistics as belonging to this category.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Even Ptolemy whose merit it was to have realized that optics, notwithstanding its profoundly geometrical character, yet requires a method essentially different from that of pure geometry [cf. A. Lejeune, Euclide et Ptolémée. Deux stades de l’optique géométrique grecque. Université de Louvain, Recueil de Travaux d’Histoire et de Philologie, ser. 3, fasc. 31 (Louvain, 1948), p. 41], nevertheless chose to ignore, or to smooth over, whatever discrepancies he found between his careful and often ingenious measurements on the one hand and the exigencies of his a priori theoretical models on the other, always favoring the latter (e.g. in his determination of the angular dimension of the visual cone (cf. ibid. pp. 41–51) as well as in his drawing up of the tables of refraction [cf. id., ‘Les tables de réfraction de Ptolémée’, in Annales de la Société Scientifique de Bruxelles, ser. 1, vol. 60 (1946), pp. 95 ff.]. Having said this much, however, I should add that there are also unmistakable methodological tensions operative in Ptolemy’s work as he is caught between his loyalty to the archetypal Euclidean conception of science and his own experimental inclinations. These ambiguities are especially manifest in his work on diplopy and on the horopter [cf. id., ‘Les recherches de Ptolémée sur la vision binoculaire’, Janus 47 (1958), pp. 79–86)]

    Google Scholar 

  26. Damianoe, Schrift über Optik, R. Schoene (ed.), (Berlin, 1897), p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Damianoe, Schrift über Optik, R. Schoene (ed.), (Berlin, 1897), 7–20.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. A. Lejeune (1948), p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  29. De aspectibus, propositions 1–3, in ‘Alkindi, Tideus und Pseudo-Euklid. Drei optische Werke’, A.A. Björnbo and S. Vogel (eds.), Abhandlungen zur Geschichte der Mathematischen Wissenschaften, vol. 26, 3 (Leipzig/Berlin, 1912) pp. 4 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Euclid, Optics, Definitions 1–7, in A Source Book in Greek Science, M.R. Cohen and I.E. Drabkin (eds.), (Cambridge, 1966), pp. 257–8.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Hero, Catoptrics, 1, in Cohen and Drabkin (1966), pp. 261–2. In his Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements the Neoplatonist Proclus (A.D. 410–485) divides optics into optics proper (including the theory of perceptual illusions), general catoptrics (which is concerned with the various ways in which light is reflected) and scenography (or applied perspective); cf. Proclus, A Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements, I,40, Glenn R. Morrow (tr.), (Princeton, 1970), p. 33.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid., pp. 263–4.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Quoted in A. Lejeune (1948), p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cf. ibid. For Aristotle’s ‘ethereal’ theory of light, cf. De anima, 2, 7, 418b 14–19.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Cf. A. Lejeune (1948), pp. 54–5.

    Google Scholar 

  37. For a similar analysis cf. A.C. Crombie, ‘The Mechanistic Hypothesis and the Scientific Study of Vision: Some Optical Ideas as a Background to the Invention of the Microscope’, in Historical Aspects of Microscopy, Papers read at a one-day Conference held by The Royal Microscopical Society at Oxford, 18 March, 1966, S. Bradbury and G.L.E. Turner (eds.), (Cambridge, 1967), p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Cf. D. Davidson, ‘Mental Events’, in Experience and Theory, L. Foster and J.W. Swanson (eds.), (Mass. University Press, 1970), p. 94.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Cf. I. Lakatos (1971), pp. 91–135.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Meyering, T.C. (1989). The Formation of Competing Optical Traditions in Early and Late Antiquity. In: Historical Roots of Cognitive Science. Synthese Library, vol 208. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2423-9_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2423-9_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7592-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2423-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics