Skip to main content

The Cartesian Cogito, Epistemic Logic and Neuroscience: Some Surprising Interrelations

  • Chapter
The Logic of Epistemology and the Epistemology of Logic

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 200))

Abstract

One cannot discuss contemporary philosophy of mind without the ghost of Descartes skulking around in the shadows. And one cannot understand Descartes without understanding his famous cogito insight, put forward for the first time publicly 350 years ago.1 Twenty-five years ago I showed what the nerve of the Cartesian insight is2. Descartes is not inferring sum from cogito, but demonstrating to himself his own existence by performing an act of thinking. The expression cogito does not mark a premise from which sum is inferred, but a thought-art which reveals (as long as it goes on) to Descartes the entity that he is. Descartes’s little skit is analogous to someone’s, say Mark Twain’s, proving his existence to a skeptic by confronting the doubter and confirming his existence to him by saying: “I exist.” Of course any other thought-act (in Descartes’s case) or language act (in Mark Twain’s case) would have done the trick equally well. This opens the door to Descartes’s dramatic gambit of attempting to doubt, nay, to deny, everything. When he then tries to deny to himself his own existence, by so doing he on the contrary proves that he exists. In Mark Twain’s case an analogous purpose is served by the language act of declaring the rumors of his demise to be exaggerated.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. René Descartes: 1637,Discours de la méthode, Ian Maire, Leiden. This paper was originally presented as my contribution to the 1987 meeting of IIP on Descartes and the Contemporary Philosophy of Mind.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Jaakko Hintikka: 1962, ‘Cogito ergo sum: Inference or Performance?’, Philosophical Review 72, 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. This immediately explains the curious temporality of Descartes’s insight. “... I had only to cease to think for an instant of time, and I should then (even although all the other things I had imagined still remained true) have no ground for believing that I can have existed in that instant. (Discours, Part IV).

    Google Scholar 

  4. For instance, the well-known criticism by Fred Feldman: 1973 (see his paper ‘On the Performatory Interpretation of the cogito’, Philosophical Review 83, 345–363) is predicated on the mistaken idea that I am trying to explain the nature of Descartes’s thesis simply by acknowledging its character as an existentially self-verifying sentence, almost as if I were trying to present a syllogism with existentially self-verifying as a middle term. This is a radical distortion of what I did in the original paper. A great deal of further argument is needed to show why and when an existentially inconsistent sentence is absurd to utter.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. See L. Chr. Lichtenberg and Fr. Kries (eds.): 1800–1803, Georg Christoph Lichtenbergs Vermischte Schriften, 1–5, Göttingen, especially 2, p. 96.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Italo Calvino: 1977, The Nonexisting Knight & The Cloven Viscount, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, New York, especially pp. 3–7.

    Google Scholar 

  7. If it is possible for someone to say, “I don’t exist”, without thereby falsifying what he is saying, how can Descartes’s thought that he doesn’t exist be self-refuting? Yet everything depends here on the precise sense of “exist”.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Jaakko Hintikka, 1969: Models for Modalities, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, chapter ‘On the Logic of Perception’

    Google Scholar 

  9. The Intentions of Intentionality, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1975, chapters 34

    Google Scholar 

  10. ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance — Individuation by Acquaintance’, in D. Pears, editor, Bertrand Russell: Critical Essays, Doubleday, Garden City, N.J., 1972, pp. 52–79.

    Google Scholar 

  11. In ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance — Identification by Acquaintance’ (note 8 above) I argued that perspectivally identified entities were roughly speaking those we are acquainted with in Bertrand Russell’s sense. For Russell, see his (1981) ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description’, in Mysticism and Logic, Longmans, London, 1918, pp. 209–232.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See Saul Kripke: 1980, Naming and Necessity, Harvard University Press. Kripke characterizes his “rigid designators” by saying that each of them necessarily refers to the same individual in every possible world in which this individual exists. But this does not tell us anything whatsoever before we know what counts (in our conceptual system) as being the same individual in different worlds.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See Bertrand Russell, Mysticism and Logic, op. cit., p. 224.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Even though it is a fundamental mistake to think that Wittgenstein in any sense denied the reality of knowability of private experiences, he certainly would not have countenanced private criteria of identification. Cf. here Merrill B. Hintikka and Jaakko Hintikka: 1986, Investigating Wittgenstein, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, ch. 10, especially sec. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  15. No wonder Descartes moved (in(the second meditation) immediately from his cogito insight to the thesis sum res cogitans.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See here also the works mentioned in note 8 above plus Jaakko Hintikka: 1976, The Semantics of Questions and the Questions of Semantics (Acta Philosophica Fennica, 28, no. 4), The Philosophical Society of Finland, Helsinki.

    Google Scholar 

  17. In the past, philosophers occasionally quarrelled about whether the subject must have recognized b in order for it to be true to say that she or he has seen b. Cf., e.g., CD. Broad, G J. Warnock and F.N. A. Vesey in Robert J. Swartz (ed.): 1965, Perceiving, Sensing, and Knowing, University of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles, pp. 29–83. The controversies were futile, however. All we have is a distinction between two different senses of the English direct-object construction “a sees b”.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See note 10 above.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See here The Semantics of Questions and the Questions of Semantics (note 16 above).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Forthcoming in Synthese Library, Kluwer, Dordrecht. My references are to a draft version of the book. See also John H.R. Maunsell, ‘Physiological Evidence for Two Visual Subsystems’, in Lucia Vaina (ed.): 1987, Matters of Intelligence, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 59–87.

    Google Scholar 

  21. David Marr’s work is summarised in his book (1982) Vision, Freeman San Francisco. See also David Marr and H.K. Nishihara: 1978, ‘Representation and Recognition of the Spatial Organization of Three-Dimensional Shapes’, Proceedings of the Royal Society London B, vol. 200 (1978), pp. 269–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Op. cit., p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Op. cit., p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Op. cit., p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. Ludwig Wittgenstein: 1953, Philosophical Investigations, Basil Black-well, Oxford, I, sees. 48–49

    Google Scholar 

  26. 1958, The Blue and Brown Books, Basil Black-well, Oxford, e.g., pp. 3, 13–14, 86–87, etc.

    Google Scholar 

  27. 1977, Remarks on Colour, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, especially I, sec. 59

    Google Scholar 

  28. Merrill B. Hintikka and Jaakko Hintikka Investigating Wittgenstein, op. cit., especially ch. 11, secs. 10–14.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Op. cit., p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Op. cit., p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  31. See W.V. Quine: 1976, ‘Worlds Away’, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 73, pp. 859–863

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. and cf. Jaakko Hintikka, ‘Quine on Who’s Who’, in Lewis E. Hahn and RA. Schupp (eds.), The Philosophy of W.V. Quine (Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 18), Open Court, LaSalle, Illinois, pp. 209–226.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Vaina, op. cit., p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Op. cit., p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Op. cit., pp. 19–20.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Op. cit., p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Op. cit., p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Endel Tulving: 1983, Elements of Episodic Memory, Clarendon Press, Oxford, with further references to the literature. The connection between Tulving’s distinction and mine was first pointed out to me by Barry Loewer (personal communication).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Op. cit., pp. 17,41,58.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Op. cit., pp. 25,35.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Cf., e.g., op. cit. p. 49: “... semantic memory develops before episodic memory. Kinsbourne and Wood (1975), for instance have pointed out that people learn ‘word meanings and such semantic information before there is any evidence of episodic remembering’...”. Tulving is not unaware of the pitfalls of the term “semantic”, however; cf. op. cit., pp. 28–29.

    Google Scholar 

  42. In chapter 5, e.g., on pp. 79–83 of op. cit. Tulving describes experiments in which the episodic vs. semantical distinction was tested by testing inter alia subjects’ memory for the meaning of words. This is not at all a representative situation. It would have been better to test the contrast by means of, e.g., comparisons between memories of events involving known and unknown people. In fact, Tulving does rely on the mirror image of such a situation, which is exemplified by the Warrington-Weiskrantz effect. (Op. cit., pp. 30–31, 94–95, 115–116.)

    Google Scholar 

  43. Cf., e.g., Stephen Stich: 1983, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science, The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Cf. David Marr and H.K. Nishihara, 1978: ‘Visual Information Processing: Artificial Intelligence and the Sensorium of Sight’, Technology Review 8, pp. 2–22, and the works mentioned in note 21 above.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Cf., e.g., Joseph Y. Halpern (ed.): 1986, Reasoning About Knowledge, Morgan Kaufmann Publishers, Los Altos, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  46. The distinction is a well-entrenched part of the folklore of AI. For an early formulation, see R. Paul, G. Falk and J.A. Feldman: 1969, ‘The Computer Representation of Simply Described Scenes’, Reports of the Stanford Artificial Intelligence Project AIM-107, Computer Science Department, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hintikka, J., Hintikka, M.B. (1989). The Cartesian Cogito, Epistemic Logic and Neuroscience: Some Surprising Interrelations. In: The Logic of Epistemology and the Epistemology of Logic. Synthese Library, vol 200. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2647-9_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2647-9_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-7923-0041-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2647-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics