Skip to main content

How To Be A Good Philosopher Of Science: A Plea For Empiricism In Matters Methodological

  • Chapter
Methodology, Metaphysics and the History of Science

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 84))

  • 130 Accesses

Abstract

It has been argued that philosophy of science in our time is basically of two types1 — speculative and analytic. Speculative philosophy of science constructs theories of the world based on the findings of the specific sciences and is continuous with science on the one hand and metaphysics on the other. Analytic philosophy of science analyzes the concepts and modes of reasoning characteristic of science and eschews speculation. However, Paul Feyerabend’s philosophy of science does not seem to fit easily into either category. For Feyerabend, philosophy of science has a rather different task than either speculation or analysis, namely to expound, criticize and defend large methodological programs for scientific progress and growth.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. But see May Brodbeck, The Nature and Function of the Philosophy of Science’, Readings in the Philosophy of Science, ed. H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck (Appleton- Century-Crofts, New York, 1953 ), pp. 3–7. Brodbeck distinguishes four meanings of ‘philosophy of science’: the socio-psychological study of science; the moral evaluation of the scientist’s role; the ‘philosophy of nature’; the logical analysis of science. Brodbeck rejects all but the last. However, it is difficult to fit Feyerabend into any of Brodbeck’s categories. Indeed, it is difficult to fit Bacon, Mill, and Popper into her categories. For Feyerabend as well as Bacon, Mill, and Popper are not merely logically analyzing science; they are recommending programs of scientific growth and procedure. Such recommendations could hardly be called metaphysical speculations, ethical evaluations or sociological investigations of science.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Richard M. Burian, ‘Scientific Realism and Incommensurability: Some Criticisms of Kuhn and Feyerabend’, this volume, pp. 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Richard M. Burian, ‘Scientific Realism, Commensurability and Conceptual Change: A Critique of Paul Feyerabend’s Philosophy of Science’, unpublished Doctoral Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Karl Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery ( Basic Books, New York, 1959 ).

    Google Scholar 

  5. For an illuminating extended discussion of this contrast, see Barry Hallen, ‘Boldness and Caution in the Methodology and Social Philosophy of Karl Popper’, unpublished Doctoral Dissertation, Boston University, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  6. 341–349; reprinted in Michael Martin, Social Science and Philosophical Analysis ( University Press of America, Washington, D.C., 1978 ), pp. 101–109.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See Israel Scheffler, Science and Subjectivity (The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., Indianapolis, 1967 ), pp. 45–66.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Michael Martin, ‘Referential Variance and Scientific Objectivity’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 22 (1971) 17–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. See Michael Martin, ‘Ontological Variance and Scientific Objectivity’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23 (1972) 252–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Cf. Michael Martin, ‘Anomaly-Recognition and Research in Science Education’, Journal for Research in Science Teaching 7 (1970) 187–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. See Marguerite Foster and Michael Martin, eds., Probability, Confirmation and Simplicity ( Odyssey Press, New York, 1966 ), pp. 233–249

    Google Scholar 

  12. Michael Martin, ‘The Falsifiability of Curve-Hypotheses’, Philosophical Studies, pp. 56–60 (1965).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1984 D. Reidel Publishing Company

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Martin, M. (1984). How To Be A Good Philosopher Of Science: A Plea For Empiricism In Matters Methodological. In: Cohen, R.S., Wartofsky, M.W. (eds) Methodology, Metaphysics and the History of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 84. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6331-3_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6331-3_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-009-6333-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-6331-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics