Skip to main content

An Invisible Nature: The Origin of Thomas Hobbes’s Civil Laws

  • Chapter
The Invisible Origins of Legal Positivism

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 52))

  • 259 Accesses

Abstract

Thomas Hobbes’ theory of law carries through the paradox of supporting binding civil laws which depend upon an invisible authorizing origin.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Reference

  1. Thomas HobbesLeviathaned. with intro. C.B. Macpherson (London: Penguin, 1968; 1651), chap. 21, 270.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Leviathanchap. 21, 272.

    Google Scholar 

  3. M.M. GoldsmithHobbes’ Science of Politics(New York and London: Columbia University Press, 1966). Also see R.S.PetersHobbes(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Leo Strauss, “The Spirit of Hobbes’ Political Philosophy,” inNatural Right and History(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), chap. 1. Also see StraussThe Political Philosophy of Hobbes: Its Basis and Genesistrans Elsa M. Sinclair (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952).

    Google Scholar 

  5. C.B. MacphersonThe Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Michael Oakeshott, “Introduction toLeviathan”in HobbesLeviathaned. Oakeshott (Oxford: Blackwell, 1946), vii-Ixvi. Reprinted inHobbes on Civil Association(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1975), 1–74. References will be made to theCivil Association edn.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Oakeshott believes that such a solitary individual does exist and is a real individual being. lbid 34. This is erroneous, l suggest, because one must ask `how is it possible for an individual human being to exist without a language?’

    Google Scholar 

  8. David GauthierThe Logic of Leviathan: The Moral and Political Theory of Thomas Hobbes(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  9. A.E. Taylor, “The Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes” inPhilosophy(1938) 13: 406–424, reprinted in ed. K.C. BrownHobbes Studies(Oxford:Basil Blackwell, 1965), 35–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Howard WarrenderThe Political Philosophy of Hobbes: His Theory of Obligation(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1957), 7, 10, 322. Also see Warrender, “A Reply to Mr. Plamenatz,” inPolitical Studies 8(1960): 48–57, reprinted in BrownHobbes Studies89–100.

    Google Scholar 

  11. F.C. HoodThe Divine Politics of Thomas Hobbes: an Interpretation of Leviathan(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1964).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Leviathanchap. 4, 100.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Thomas HobbesElements of Law: Natural and Politic.Ed. with pref and critical notes, Ferdinand Tonnies and with intro. by M. M. Goldsmith (London: Frank Cass; 2nd ed. 1969; 1889). Critical ed’n by Howard Warrender, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), part 1, chap. 2, sect. 12, (hereinafter cited as 1.2.12).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Leviathanchap 26, 313.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See esp.Leviathan, chap 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Leviathanchap. 1, 85.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See generally, Frederick CoplestonA History of Philosophyvol. 3, bk. 1 (New York/London: Doubleday, 1946; 1985), 39–42, 46–48.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Leviathanchap. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Leviathanchap. 4, 105.

    Google Scholar 

  20. For Hobbes’ view of the scientific method, see esp. Copleston, chap. 5, 115–17. Hobbes is quick to note that the faculty of “reckoning” for the Romans lay in theNominaor names for theRationcinatioor accounting of money(Rations). Leviathanchap. 4, 106. It is interesting and ironic that contemporary legal analysis in common law jurisdictions gives great weight, at least in form, to theratio decidendiof a legal judgment.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Copleston, 109. Emphasis added.

    Google Scholar 

  22. have argued inThe Phenomenology of Modern Legal Discourse(Aldershot/Brookfield: Dartmouth/ Ashgate, 1998), chap. 5, that this view has a Husserlian flavour to it although, for Husserl, the subject intuitively thinks. Accordingly, meaning is provisional and subject to revision for Husserl. For Hobbes, one has a concept rather than a thought of a referent. Hobbes’ view is more Platonic in this respect.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Copleston, bk. 1, vol. 3, 109–10.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Leviathanchap. 4, 100.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Leviathanchap. 14, 197–98.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Leviathanchap. 26, 317.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Leviathanchap. 27, 225.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Leviathanchap. 17, 226.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See, e.g.Leviathanchap. 13, 187; chap. 30, 378.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Leviathanchap. 14, 190.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Leviathanchap. 14, 197. InDe Civevol. 3 of Clarendon Edition of the Philosophical Works of Thomas Hobbes, critical edn. by Howard Warrender (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983; 1651), Part 1, chap. 2, sect. 12. Entitled in 1st edn. asPhilosophical Rudiments concerning Government and Society.Hobbes explains that one cannot contract with another unless the party accepts an offer. But beasts can neither make nor accept an offer.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Leviathanchap. 13, 186.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Elements of Law1.5.5.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Elements of Law1.5.13.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Elements of Law;1.5.14.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Leviathanchap. 4, 109.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Leviathanchap. 4, 105.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Leviathanchap. 4, 106.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Leviathan“introduction,” 81.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Leviathanchap. 15, 216. Emphasis added.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Leviathanchap. 16, 217.

    Google Scholar 

  43. I refer to the male gender because Hobbes intends that his claims only concern men. Hobbes continually describes the pyramidal organization of offices as “patriarchal.” So, even if women ever occupied an office, their role, which determines their decisions, would come from a patriarchal context.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Leviathanchap. 16, 217.

    Google Scholar 

  45. De Cive2.12.4.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Leviathanchap. 17, 227.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Leviathanchap. 26, 317. Emphasis added.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  49. De Cive2.12.5.

    Google Scholar 

  50. De Cive2.6.8.

    Google Scholar 

  51. De Cive2.8.5.

    Google Scholar 

  52. De Cive2.6.8.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Leviathanchap. 5, 116.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Leviathanchap. 26, 317.

    Google Scholar 

  55. “Epistle Dedicatory”toLeviathan 75.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Leviathanchap. 21, 264–65. Emphasis added.

    Google Scholar 

  57. De Cive2.12.1.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Leviathanchap. 30, 388.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Hobbes, ADialogue between a Philosopher and a Student of the Common Laws of England.Ed. & intro. Joseph Cropsey (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1971; 1681), “Of Soveraign Power,” 58–9 (10). The page references will be to the Cropsey edn. with the original pagination in (¡­), as noted by Cropsey.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Dialogue“Of Soveraign Power,” 59 (11).

    Google Scholar 

  61. Leviathanchap. 16, 220–21.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Leviathanchap. 25, 306.Cf. De Cive3.18.1.

    Google Scholar 

  63. De Cive2.6.13; 2.6.18.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Leviathanchap. 18, 238.

    Google Scholar 

  65. SeeDe Cive2.6.13; 2.9.3.

    Google Scholar 

  66. De Cive2.8.5.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Leviathanchap. 18, 231.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Leviathanchap. 18, 232.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Leviathanchap. 15, 122–23.

    Google Scholar 

  70. A.P. MartinichThe Two Gods of Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes on Religion and Politics(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 93.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  71. Elements of Law1.15.8.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Leviathanchap.15202; De Cive2.6.1;Dialogue73 (36).

    Google Scholar 

  73. Leviathanchap. 26, 315.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Leviathanchap. 26, 318. When Hobbes described the first fundamental law of nature early in theLeviathanhe was referring to the early stage of the natural condition when creatures did not share a language. Because of the consequences of the language-less condition, the first principle of living should be “That every man, ought to endeavour Peace, as farte as he has hope of obtaining it; and when he cannot obtain it, that he may seek, and use, all helps, and advantages of Warre.”Leviathanchap. 14, 190.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Leviathanchap. 14, 190.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Leviathanchap. 30, 376.

    Google Scholar 

  77. De Cive2.14.21.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Even Howard Warrender misses the point that the natural duties arise before the creatures in the natural condition begin to understand each other through shared conventions about marks and sounds. WarrenderPolitical Philosophy of Hobbes1–79. Warrender does claim that the citizen’s obligation to obey the state’s laws arises prior to and independent of the creation of the state. But Wartender, missing the importance granted to language as the distinguishing factor between the natural condition and civil society, and associates the natural condition with the first act of culture when creatures make covenants with each other. Wartender ignores Hobbes’ focus upon the inability of the creatures in the prior condition to speak or write through a language.

    Google Scholar 

  79. F.C. HoodThe Divine Politics145.

    Google Scholar 

  80. See generally ibid., 210.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Leviathanchap. 29, 367.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Leviathanchap. 21.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Leviathanchap. 21, 268.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Leviathanchap. 14, 199.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Leviathanchap. 21, 269.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Leviathanchap. 14, 198.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Leviathanchap. 14, 199.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Leviathanchap. 21, 270.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Leviathanchap. 21, 272.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Leviathanchap. 21, 268.

    Google Scholar 

  91. De Cive1.3.32.

    Google Scholar 

  92. De Cive1.4.11.

    Google Scholar 

  93. De Cive1.4.21.

    Google Scholar 

  94. De Cive2.14.14.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  96. This contrasts with Martin Luther (1483–1546) who had earlier claimed that God is infinite inwardness. AlsoseeKantCritique of Judgmenttrans. Werner S. Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987; 1790), Pt 1.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Elements of Lax;2.10.10.

    Google Scholar 

  98. De Cive2.14.15.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Leviathanchap. 4, 105.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Dialogue“Of Soveraign Power,” 72–3 (41).

    Google Scholar 

  101. Leviathanchap. 26, 312.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Dialogue“Of Soveraign Power,” 73 (36–37).

    Google Scholar 

  103. De Cive1.2.12.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Leviathanchap. 14, 197.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Dialogue“Of Soveraign Power,” 75 (41).

    Google Scholar 

  106. Leviathanchap. 26, 323.

    Google Scholar 

  107. According to John Knox (c.1513–1572), if the sovereign itself were unjust, the citizenry had the right to depose the immoral sovereign. The citizen may interpret the civil laws in terms of `who is saved’ and ‘who is damned.’

    Google Scholar 

  108. Leviathanchap. 26, 319.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Leviathanchap.26, 322.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Dialogue“Of Soveraign Power,” 58–9 (10).

    Google Scholar 

  111. Dialogue 85–6(60–1), 62–3 (17–8).

    Google Scholar 

  112. Dialogue“Of Soveraign Power,” 96 (80), 61–2 (16);Leviathanchap. 26, 313; 316–17.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Dialogue“Of Soveraign Power,” 61 (16). When James I had claimed in theProhibitions del Roythat he too was authorized to resolve disputes amongst the citizenry because “the law was founded upon reason, and that he and others had reason, as well as judges,” CokeCJreported his own reply to the King in these words, “¡­ true it was, that God had endowed his Majesty with excellent science, and great endowments of nature; but His Majesty was not learned in the laws of his realm of England, and causes which concern the life, or inheritance, or goods, or fortunes of his subjects, are not to be decided by natural reason but by the artificial reason and judgment of the law, which law is an actwhich requires long study and experiencebefore a man can attain to the cognizance of it¡­.” (1608), 12Co. Rep.63, 77 E.R.1342 (K.B.). Emphasis added. Coke’s theory of law is examined in William E. ConklinIn Defence of Fundamental Rights(Alphen aan den Rijn: Sijtoff & Noordhof, 1979), 13–53.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Dialogue“Of Courts,” 79 (47).

    Google Scholar 

  115. Leviathanchap. 26, 315.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Dialogue“Of the Law of Reason,” 55 (4).

    Google Scholar 

  117. Dialogue“Of Soveraign Power,” 71 (32).

    Google Scholar 

  118. Dialogue“Of the Law of Reason,” 55 (4).

    Google Scholar 

  119. Dialogue“Of the law of Reason,” 68 (28).

    Google Scholar 

  120. They were called such even in Hobbes’ day. For a discussion of their import today see William E. Conklin“Pickinand its Applicability to Canada”in University of Toronto Law Journal25 (1975): 193–214.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Leviathanchap. 26, 322.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Leviathanchap. 21, 268. Hobbes’ emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  123. De Cive2.6.13.

    Google Scholar 

  124. De Cive2.14.20.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Leviathanchap. 29, 367.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Leviathanchap. 18, 232.

    Google Scholar 

  127. See Conklin, “The Origins of the Law of Sedition,” inCriminal Law Quarterly 15(1972–73): 277–300.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Leviathanchap. 30, 381. And again, “for they are bound, every man to every man, to Own, and be reputed Author of all, that he that already is their Soveraigne, shall do, and judge fit to be done: so that any one man dissenting, all the rest should break their Covenant made to that man, which is injustice.”Leviathanchap. 18, 229.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Leviathanchap. 8, 231.

    Google Scholar 

  130. Leviathanchap. 18, 229.

    Google Scholar 

  131. Leviathanchap. 21, 272.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Drawing from a distinction of Roland Barthes, a myth is a second-level semiological system or metalanguage constructed from prior configurations of signs. Roland Barthes, “Myth Today,” inMythologies(Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1957), 109–59. Also see Barthes, “From Work to Text,” in Josue U. HarariText and Strategies: Perspectives in Post-Structuralist Criticism(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1979), 73–81; “Theory of the Text,” inUntying the Text: A Post-Structuralist Readered. Robert Young (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1981), 31–47. This view of myth is modernist in that it fails to account for the presentative character of symbols and of rituals in the totemic culture of early Greece, as elaborated in chapters one and three above. This is also discussed in Conklin, “Hegel, the Author and Authority in Sophocles’Antigone in ed. Leslie G. RubinJustice vs. Law in Greek Political Thought(New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 1997), 129–51.

    Google Scholar 

  133. De Cive3.15.14.

    Google Scholar 

  134. Leviathanchap. 6, 124.

    Google Scholar 

  135. Leviathanchap. 29, 370–71.

    Google Scholar 

  136. I am drawing here from Jacques Lacan’s explanation of the language of the unconscious amongst the mad.

    Google Scholar 

  137. “An Answer to a Book published by Dr. Bramhall called the `Catching of the Leviathan’,” inEnglish Works of Thomas Hobbes (EW) 4p. 292.

    Google Scholar 

  138. Leviathanchap. 30, 376.

    Google Scholar 

  139. Leviathanchap. 32, 410.

    Google Scholar 

  140. Leviathanchap. 33, 415.

    Google Scholar 

  141. Leviathanchap. 31, 396.

    Google Scholar 

  142. Leviathanchap. 31, 396.

    Google Scholar 

  143. Leviathanchap. 34, 440.

    Google Scholar 

  144. Leviathanchap. 26, 332.

    Google Scholar 

  145. Leviathanchap. 26, 333.

    Google Scholar 

  146. Leviathanchap. 36, 459.

    Google Scholar 

  147. Leviathanchap. 14, 197.

    Google Scholar 

  148. Leviathanchap. 33, 426.

    Google Scholar 

  149. Leviathanchap. 31, 396. Also see chap. 26, 319; chap. 32, 409.

    Google Scholar 

  150. Leviathanchap. 33, 427.

    Google Scholar 

  151. Leviathanchap. 11, 167; chap. 12, 170.Elements of Law1.11.2;Elements of Philosophy. The First Section Concerning the Body EW 126.1, p. 412.

    Google Scholar 

  152. De Cive2.15.14.

    Google Scholar 

  153. Leviathanchap. 16, 221–22; chap. 42, 534–37. Cf.De Cive3.15.2.

    Google Scholar 

  154. Leviathanchap. 31, 4546.

    Google Scholar 

  155. Leviathanchap. 34, 430.

    Google Scholar 

  156. De Cive3.15.14.

    Google Scholar 

  157. De Cive3.15.5.

    Google Scholar 

  158. De Cive3.16.18.

    Google Scholar 

  159. Interestingly, Warrender seems to suggest just such an intellectualization. See WarrenderPolitical Philosophy 250.

    Google Scholar 

  160. De Cive1.4.33.

    Google Scholar 

  161. Leviathanchap. 26, 314.

    Google Scholar 

  162. WarrenderPolitical Philosophy166–76; Oakeshott, “The Moral Life in the Writings of Thomas Hobbes,” inCivil Association103–113.

    Google Scholar 

  163. Leviathanchap. 31, 399.

    Google Scholar 

  164. De Cive3.16.1.

    Google Scholar 

  165. Leviathan chap.11, 168.

    Google Scholar 

  166. Leviathanchap. 4, 101.

    Google Scholar 

  167. Leviathanchap. 23, 291. Emphasis added.

    Google Scholar 

  168. Leviathanchap. 17, 227. Hobbes’ emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  169. Leviathanchap. 26, 328.

    Google Scholar 

  170. SeeDe Cive3.15.17.

    Google Scholar 

  171. Leviathanchap. 26, 322.

    Google Scholar 

  172. Leviathanchap. 26, 323.

    Google Scholar 

  173. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Conklin, W.E. (2001). An Invisible Nature: The Origin of Thomas Hobbes’s Civil Laws. In: The Invisible Origins of Legal Positivism. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 52. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0808-2_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0808-2_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-0282-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-0808-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics