Skip to main content

The Historical Process and its Explanation: Karl Popper and his Debtors

  • Chapter
Philosophy, History and Politics

Part of the book series: Melbourne International Philosophy Series ((MIPS,volume 1))

  • 88 Accesses

Abstract

A schematic classification of different directions of philosophies of history could point out that “classical “philosophical views are concerned with the nature of the historical processes, its components, its meaning, and its goal. In the classical approach, historical understanding is related to an assessment of the historical process. The philosophical problem of history is twofold; both aspects of the problem emerge also in Hegel’s discussion of the two sides of the term “history” as the course of events and as its understanding. The classical tradition, in this sense, refers to Hegel, Marx, Comte, Croce, Bradley, etc. who shaped its image. Measured by the general trend of the classical tradition, the more recent interest in history seems to take a different direction which might be characterized, loosely, as methodological.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Cf., respectively, “The Function of General Laws in History”, Readings in Philosophical Analysis, edited by H. Feigl and W. Sellars, New York, 1948, pp. 459–471, and Laws and Explanation in History, Oxford, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  2. On Collingwood see Patrick Gardiner, The Nature of Historical Explanation, London, 1952, pp. 46, 47, 77, 115; Oakeshott is discussed on pp. 29–32, 35, 80. On Collingwood see also W. B. Gallie, Philosophy and the Historical Understanding, London 1964, pp. 17, 18, 46.

    Google Scholar 

  3. C. G. Hempel, “Scientific Explanation”, Voice of America Forum Lectures, Philosophy of Science Series, No.11, p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Karl R. Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, London, 1961, p. 160. “Historism” or “Historicism” is an ambiguous term. It is clear that Popper’s understanding of the concept is based on a selection of one possible connotation of it. As to the various meanings, consult Karl Heussi, Die Krisis des Historismus, Tübingen, 1932.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Popper, ibid., pp. 27–28.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid., p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid., p. 146.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See ibid.,p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., p. 128.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., pp. 65, 67.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., pp. 80–81.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See ibid., p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., p. 149.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Here lies also the origin of the ethico-theological concept, “Situationsethik”.

    Google Scholar 

  26. P. Gardiner, The Nature of Historical Explanation, London 1952, p. 49.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid., p. 45.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., pp. 138–139.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., p. 139.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid., p. 98.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., p. 95.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid., p. 82.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Gallie, W. Z. Philosophy and the Historical Understanding, New York, 1964, pp. 118–119.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid., p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid., p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid., p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ibid., p. 33. Professor E. Gellner observes on this issue “Gallie is not merely a philosopher concerned with contingency, he has something like a passion for it”. See his “The Concept of Story”, Ratio, Vol. IX, June 1967, pp. 49ff.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ibid., p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ibid., p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ibid., p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid., p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid., p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ibid., p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1976 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rotenstreich, N. (1976). The Historical Process and its Explanation: Karl Popper and his Debtors. In: Philosophy, History and Politics. Melbourne International Philosophy Series, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1351-2_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1351-2_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-1743-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-1351-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics