Skip to main content

Ethics and the Problem of Value in the Vienna Circle

  • Chapter
Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 133))

Abstract

It is known that problems of ethics and the philosophy of value (understood as theoretical problems) played a small or peripheral role in the Vienna Circle: according to participants like Viktor Kraft and Heinrich Neider, they did not constitute topics in the discussions proper (cf. Kraft 1973, Haller and Rutte 1977). On the other hand, something has been rediscovered which had been repressed for a while in the post-war empiricist, analytical philosophy, or had simply not been talked about, and which, probably due to the ‘positivism-dispute’ of the mid-’60’s, the younger generation did not even notice1—namely that, to different degrees and according to their individual temperament, most members of the Vienna Circle were politically engaged for social reform, even zealously so, and that all of them felt themselves to be free-thinkers and advocates of the enlightenment who intended to educate the broader population (as was recently documented in great detail by Friedrich Stadler (1982b)). So there seems to be a correspondence of sorts (perhaps even of a compensatory nature) between the strict rejection of objective values and the objective justification of values, shared by all thinkers of this group, and their forceful declamatory moral and political will, their urge to promote the liberation and increased happiness of humanity. Just this mixture of destruction and engagement would appear to have been particularly explosive for outsiders and opponents of the group.

Notes

First published as ‘Ethik und Werturteilsproblematik im Wiener Kreis’ in Von Bolzano zu Wittgenstein. Zur Tradition der österreichischen Philosophie, Hrsg. J. C. Nyiri, Schriftenreihe der Wittgenstein-Gesellschaft Bd. 12, Teil 2, © 1986, Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, Wien, pp. 162–172. Translated with kind permission of Verlag Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky and the author by T. E. Uebel.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Compare the discussion between A. Beckermann, R. Hegselmann and W. R. Köhler in Analyse und Kritik 1 (1979) no. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See Carnap 1928a, Carnap-Hahn-Neurath 1929, Hahn 1930, Neurath 1931c, and the posthumously published Schlick 1952 and 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  3. For example, without mention of Schlick’s name in section 6 of Neurath 1932a. Criticism of Schlick’s hedomism is suggested also in Menger 1934 and explicitly formulated in Kraft 1937—again without the mention of his name. Compare also the summary in Kraft 1950,2nd ed., ch. “Values”.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Oskar Morgenstern already published a remakable appreciation of Menger in this respect in his 1936.

    Google Scholar 

  5. The following reconstruction is based on Schlick 1930b, sects. I.5, I.7–11, I.12, IV.1, IV.3–4, IV.6 (1984, pp. 60f., 63f., 66ff., 70f., 74,112f., 115f., 118,122f.).

    Google Scholar 

  6. The following is based on Kraft 1937 (1951, esp. ch. IV, also chs. II, 1 and in, 4.5). See also Kraft’s summary of his standpoint in his 1950, ch. “Values”.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Kraft 1937 (1951, p. 187: “Bestimmung einer … Stellungnahme durch einen Gegenstand ganz allgemein”).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Hegselmann 1984, sect. 4; later on, Hegselmann himself concedes that these distinctions were already drawn by Schlick.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Compare his conversations with Schlick and Waismann, published as Waismann 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Kutschera 1982, p. 187. I refer to my reconstruction of Schlick’s views in part II of this paper: Schlick bases his explication attempt precisely on the culturally determined antagonistic multiplicity of moral evaluations (Schlick 1930b, sect. 4.4) and thus he stresses that that is called ‘good’ in a society (or culture) of which this society believes that it is conducive for its wellbeing. Thus mutually incompatible modes of behaviour are called ‘good’ dependent on the society, culture and epoch, but the meaning of the expression ‘good’ nevertheless remains the same.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Compare my discussion of this problem in Rutte 1985 where I refer to Janik and Toulmin 1973 in which Wittgenstein’s ethical concerns are placed in the centre of the interpretation.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1991 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rutte, H. (1991). Ethics and the Problem of Value in the Vienna Circle. In: Uebel, T.E. (eds) Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 133. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3182-7_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3182-7_11

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-5404-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-3182-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics