Skip to main content

The Why and How of Explanation: An Analytical Exposition

  • Chapter
Explanation

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 302))

  • 412 Accesses

Abstract

Heinrich Hertz and Steven Weinberg — two illustrious physicists separated by a century — exemplify by their respective views of physics one of the crucial transitions in philosophy that this century of science has undergone. We are concerned here with the role assigned to theories, their constituting laws and consequently the criteria by which they are supposed to be compared and evaluated. Should a theory enable us to be solely “in advance of the facts,” as Hertz had stipulated [Hertz (1894) 1956], p.1, or should it aim at what seems to be a rather loftier objective: increasing our understanding of “why… [the world] is the way it is,” as Weinberg demanded [Weinberg (1992) 1994], p.219? The tension is then between on the one hand successful prediction based on appropriate representation of phenomena and on the other hand explanatory power grounded in schemes of explanation.

The most direct, and in a sense the most important, problem which our conscious knowledge of nature should enable us to solve is the anticipation of future events, so that we may arrange our present affairs in accordance with such anticipation. Heinrich Hertz The Principles of Mechanics [Hertz (1894) 1956], p.1.

Once again I repeat: the aim of physics at its most fundamental level is not just to describe the world but to explain why it is the way it is. Steven Weinberg Dreams of a Final Theory [Weinberg (1992) 1994], p.219.

At the end of this century we can seriously argue that, although metaphysics and theology may serve as sources of inspiration or consolation, intellectually illuminating explanations are to be found in the realms of natural science. It is not necessary to depart from science to have genuine understanding of the world and what transpires within it. Wesley Salmon Causality and Explanation [Salmon 1998], p.91.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Allen, C., Bekoff, M. and Lauder, G. (eds.), (1998). Nature’s Purpose: Analyses of Function and Design in Biology. Cambridge, Massachusetts: the MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Baird, D., Hughes, R. I. G. and Nordmann, A. (eds.), (1997). Heinrich Hertz: Classical Physicist, Modern Philosopher. Dordrecht, Boston, London, Boston: Studies Series V. 198, Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Brandon, R. N., (1998). “Biological Teleology: Questions and Explanations,” in [Allen et àl. 1998], pp.79–97.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Carnap, R., (1966). An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Gardner, M. (ed.), New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Glymour, C., (1984). “Explanation and Realism,” in [Leplin 1984], pp.173–192.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Hacking, I., (1983). Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Hempel, C. G., (1965). Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: the Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Hempel, C. G. and Oppenheim, P., ([1948] 1965). “Studies in the Logic of Explanation,” in [Hempel 1965], pp.245–95.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Hertz, H., ([1894] 1956). The Principles of Mechanics Presented in a New Form. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Hon, G., (1997). “Hertz’s Study of Propagation vs. Rutherford’s Study of Structure: Two Modes of Experimentation and Their Theoretical Underpinnings,” in [Baird et àl. 1997], pp.59–72.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Hon, G., (2000). “The Limits of Experimental Method: Experimenting on an Entangled System — The Case of Biophysics,” in Carrier, M., Massey, G. J. and Reutsche, L. (eds.). Science at Century’s End: Philosophical Questions on the Progress and Limits of Science. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press, pp.284–307.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Houston, J., (1994). Reported Miracles, A Critique of Hume. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. Hume, D., ([1748] 1993). “Of Miracles,” in his An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, section X.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Humphreys, W. C., (1968). Anomalies and Scientific Theories. San Francisco: Freemann, Cooper and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Kitcher, P., (1989). “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World,” in [Kitcher and Salmon 1989], pp.410–505.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Kitcher, P., (1993). The Advancement of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Kitcher, P., and Salmon, W. C. (eds.). (1989). Scientific Explanation. vol. 13, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Kuhn, T., (1977). “Concepts of Cause in the Development of Physics,” in his The Essential Tension. Chicago, London: Chicago University Press, pp.21–30.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Leplin, J., (ed.). (1984). Scientific Realism. Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Lipton, P., (1992). “The Seductive-Nomological Model,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 23: 691–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Mach, E., (1974). The Science of Mechanics: A Critical and Historical Account of Its Development. McCormack, T. J. (tr.), La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  22. McMullin, E., (1984). “The ideals of explanation in natural science,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 9: 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Millikan, R. A., (1916). “A Direct Photoelectric Determination of Planck’s ‘h’,”Physical Review, 7: 355–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Millikan, R. A., (1922). The Electron. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press (7th impres.).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Nagel, E., ([1961] 1979). The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. London and Henley: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Newton, I., ([1687] 1995). Principia. Motte, A. (tr.), Amherst, New York, Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Nobel Lectures, (1965). Physics 1922–1941. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Nobel Lectures, (1967). Physics 1901–1921. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Pais, A., (1983). “Subtle is the Lord…” The Science and Life of Albert Einstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Redhead, M., (1990). “Explanation in Physics,” in D. Knowles (ed.). Explanation and its Limits. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp.135–154.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Salmon, W. C., (1984). Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Salmon, W. C., (1990). Four Decades of Scientific Explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Salmon, W. C., (1998). Causality and Explanation. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  34. Scheffller, I., (1957). “Explanation, Prediction, and Abstraction,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 7: pp.293–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Schrödinger, E., ([1954] 1984). “The Philosophy of Experiment,” in his Collected Papers, Volume 4: General Scientific and Popular Papers. Wien: The Austrian Academy of Sciences, pp.558–568.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Stachel, J., (ed.) (1998). Einstein’s Miraculous Year. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Stuewer, R. H., (1970). “Non-Einsteinian Interpretations of the Photoelectric Effect,” in R. H. Stuewer (ed.). Historical and Philosophical Perspectives of Science. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. V. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp.246–263.

    Google Scholar 

  38. van Fraassen, B., ([1980] 1990). The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  39. van Fraassen, B., (1989). Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  40. von Wright, G. H., (1971). Explanation and Understanding. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Weinberg, S., ([1992] 1994). Dreams of A Final Theory. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Wittgenstein, L., ([1921] 1978). Tractatus Logico Philosopicus. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hon, G. (2001). The Why and How of Explanation: An Analytical Exposition. In: Hon, G., Rakover, S.S. (eds) Explanation. Synthese Library, vol 302. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9731-9_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9731-9_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5827-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9731-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics