Skip to main content

What Can We Do “In Principle”?

  • Chapter
Logic and Scientific Methods

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 259))

Abstract

It is characteristic of some quite important discourses in mathematics, having to do with computability and constructivity, to appeal to what appear to be possibilities of human thought and action, where, however, these possibilities go beyond what is “practically” possible. In particular, they do not rest on actual human abilities. Such possibilities are what I have in mind in asking what we can “in principle” do. Such possibilities are also invoked about nonhuman agents, in particular computers. I am primarily concerned, however, with real agents, human beings like you and me and computers like the ones we have on our desks, or at most supercomputers. But talk about the “in principle” capabilities of real agents is roughly equivalent to talk about the capabilities of ideal agents.

In philosophy it is can in particular that we seem so often to uncover, just when we had thought some problem settled, grinning residually up at us like the frog at the bottom of the beer mug.

J.L. Austin, “Ifs and cans1

Earlier versions of this paper were presented as the Skolem Lecture, University of Oslo, and to philosophy colloquia at Stanford and UCLA. I have received valuable comments from a number of hearers; I am painfully aware of not having done justice to all of them. Special thanks are owed to Joseph Almog, Tyler Burge, John Carriero, Solomon Feferman, Dagfinn Føllesdal, David Kaplan, Per Martin-Löf, and Grigori Mints. The earlier versions of the paper were written while I was a Fellow of the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, with the support of the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation. I wish to thank both institutions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Philosophical Papers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961), p.231.

    Google Scholar 

  2. In the course of explaining the notion of necessity that concerns him, Alvin Plantinga remarks of “leaping tall buildings in a single bound or ... travelling faster than a speeding bullet”, “These things are impossible for us; but not in the broadly logical sense” (The Nature of Necessity (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974), p.2). In talking of “jumping”, I am assuming that the jumper relies on his own power and does not use such aids as balloons. It’s not clear that all talk of jumping satisfies this constraint; consider (where the problem is the downward journey rather than reaching a height) parachute jumping.

    Google Scholar 

  3. The time demands of computing 257729 should not have daunted the Elves of The Lord of the Rings, although it is hard to imagine one of them devoting himself to such an undramatic task. The space demands might have posed a problem.

    Google Scholar 

  4. I ignore possible shortcuts, but the fact that the problem is NP-complete shows that there are serious limits of what they can accomplish.

    Google Scholar 

  5. S.C. Kleene, Introduction to Metamathematics (New York: Van Nostrand, 1952), p.136, emphases mine.

    Google Scholar 

  6. S.C. Kleene, Introduction to Metamathematics (New York: Van Nostrand, 1952), , p.47, emphases again mine. In formalized intuitionistic mathematics, it is possible to prove AV A for quantifier-free A, and then derive it for any A containing only bounded quantifiers. The pro makes essential use of primitive recursion, but not in any very strong form. It suggests that it may be possible to look at the grounds for the truth of this restricted law of excluded middle in a different way.

    Google Scholar 

  7. For simplicity I will assume that the procedure is deterministic and can thus yield at most one number as output. Functions of more than one argument can be accommodated by conventions about the representation of n-tuples of numbers.It can of course happen that the procedure does not yield a number value for any number argument; that is f is undefined for all numbers. Moreover, for a given argument we may not be able to determine whether or not the procedure terminates. That, for a given canonical form, it is not effectively decidable whether a procedure terminates is one of the basic results of the theory of computability.

    Google Scholar 

  8. In fact, sometimes it is only this direction that is called Church’s Thesis, for example by Kleene, op. cit., p.300. The equivalence fits better with Church’s original formulation. He states that he is proposing a “definition of effective calculability” as either A-definability or general recursiveness (“An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory”, American Journal of Mathematics 58 (1936), 345–363, p.90 of the reprint in Martin Davis (ed.), The Undecidable (Hewlett, N.Y.: Raven Press, 1965); cf. also p.100 and “An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory: Preliminary report” (abstract), Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 41 (1935), 332–333). On the other hand Church’s most developed argument, in §7 of the paper, is for the claim that all effectively calculable functions are recursive.

    Google Scholar 

  9. In the Turing machine case, the machine is in a “terminal state”; in the case of the formalism of recursive functions, we have reached an equation of the form f(n) = m, where f is the principal function letter.

    Google Scholar 

  10. To be sure, this formulation fits best with an embedding of the notion of general recursiveness in classical mathematics. A constructivist would demand a constructive proof that the computation terminates in general. Cf. Kleene, op. cit., p.319.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Van Dantzig writes, “Modern physics implies an upper limit, by far surpassed by 101010, for numbers which actually can be constructed in this way.” (“Is 101010 a finite number?” Dialectica 9 (1955–56), 273 277, p.273). This point was later developed further by Robin Gandy. Although van Dan zig’s point of view is akin to what is now called strict finitism, he does not propose to ba sh exponentiation from mathematics; rather he argues for a kind of relativity of the notion of natural number and the irreducibility of formal expressions involving functors introduced by primitive recursion to canonical 0 — S numerals, or even to expressions introduced earlier in a chain of primitive recursions. These ideas are developed in more recent strict finitist writing.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Such a view is usually attributed to Brouwer, not unreasonably in spite of the strongly naturalistic tendencies in his philosophy. Cf. the remarks below on Heyting.

    Google Scholar 

  13. John Carriero asked the reasonable question whether some notion of human capacity in principle already underlies the conception of mathematical construction in Euclid. Certainly lines, for example, are thought of in traditional geometry as indefinitely extendible, and we naturally think of the constructions postulated by Euclid as indefinitely iterable. Euclid’s language in stating his postulates seems to me quite reserved; for example postulate 2 is stated “To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line”. (T.L. Heath, The Thirteen Books of Euclid’s Elements, 2d ed. (Cambridge University Press, 1926), vol. 1, p.154.) Although verbs of action are used, nothing is said about what this implies. The question is not addressed in Heath’s commentary on Euclid or a couple of others I have consulted.

    Google Scholar 

  14. David Hilbert, “Mathematische Probleme”, Nachrichten von der Königlichen Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, 1900, 253–297, Problem 10, my translation.

    Google Scholar 

  15. David Hilbert and Wilhelm Ackermann, Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik (Berlin: Springer, 1928), p.73, translation from Robin Gandy, “The confluence of ideas in 1936,” in Rolf Herken (ed.), The Universal Turing Machine: A Half-Century Survey (Oxford University Press, 1988), pp.55–111, at p.62.

    Google Scholar 

  16. “An informal exposition of proofs of Gödel’s theorem and Church’s theorem,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic 4 (1939), 53–60, p.225 of the reprint in The Undecidable.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Gandy, op. cit., pp.66–7, quoted from J. von Neumann, “Zur Hilbertschen Beweistheorie,” Mathematische Zeitschrift 26 (1927), 1–46; I have modified Gandy’s translation.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. A. Heyting, “The intuitionist foundations of mathematics,” in Paul Benacerraf and Hilary Putnam (eds.), Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings (2d ed., Cambridge University Press, 1983), p.54. (Translation from Erkenntnis 2 (1931).)

    Google Scholar 

  19. E.g. ibid., p.53.

    Google Scholar 

  20. “The philosophical basis of intuitionistic logic” (1973), in Truth and Other Enigmas (London: Duckworth, 1978), p.224, emphases mine.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. the opening remarks in “Wang’s paradox” (1975), in Truth and Other Enigmas, p.248.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Crispin Wright, “Strict finitism,” Synthese 51 (1982), 203–282, cited according to the reprint in Realism, Meaning, and Truth, 2d ed. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993);

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Alexander George, “The conveyability of intuitionism: An essay in mathematical cognition,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 17 (1988), 133–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. “Strict finitism,” p.113. P should generalize readily to other activities than verifying or falsifying statements; in the text I understand it in this generalized way.

    Google Scholar 

  25. In spite of these reservations, Wright curiously appeals to P in another essay in the same volume where in principle capabilities are at issue; see Realism, Meaning, and Truth, 2d ed., p.326.

    Google Scholar 

  26. We are talking about jumping over the Eiffel Tower; the fact that a bird might be able to fly over it is presumably irrelevant. Cf. note 2.

    Google Scholar 

  27. I should make clear that I do not claim to be refuting this view. For present purposes it should suffice to observe that it would not be acceptable to either Dummett or Wright.

    Google Scholar 

  28. For example “Mathematical intuition,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society N.S. 80 (1979–80), 145–168, pp.158–159.

    Google Scholar 

  29. “On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem,” Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society (2) 42 (1936–7), 230–265, cited according to the reprint in The Undecidable.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., p.135.

    Google Scholar 

  31. This formulation, as well as (2.1) and (2.2), are from Wilfried Sieg, “Mechanical procedures and mathematical experience,” in Alexander George (ed.), Mathematics and Mind (Oxford University Pres, 1994), p.93. I am much indebted to this article as well as the one by Gandy cited in note 15.

    Google Scholar 

  32. In crediting Turing with a theorem at this point, Gandy anticipated Sieg, but Sieg’s statement, given here, is more precise.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Gandy and Sieg rightly emphasize that Turing in §9 was not analyzing computation by a machine, but “mechanical” computation by a human. It is another task, undertaken by Gandy in another paper, to analyze the notion of computation by a mechanical device.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Such an inquiry might be relevant to the justification of the assumptions; cf. Gödel’s questioning of (1.2) (Collected Works, volume II, Publications 1938–1974 , Solomon Feferman et al, eds. (Oxford University Press, 1990), p.306), and Sieg’s (in my view correct) defense of Turing, op. cit., p.98.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cf. Christos H. Papadimitriou, Computational Complexity (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1993), pp.6–7.The remarks in the text do not, I think, contradict Gödel’s claim that the notion of computability has an absolute character, in the context of classical mathematics. (See in particular “Remarks before the Princeton Bicentennial Conference on Problems in Mathematics,” in Collected Works, II, 150–153.) Turing computability was meant to answer to certain mathematical demands. Once one admits primitive recursive functions as computable (or, indeed, much less) and applies the principle “Finiteness is sufficient”, then one is forced to the conclusion that all general recursive functions are computable. And the latter principle was certainly very well motivated from a mathematical point of view. More constrained notions question either “Finiteness is sufficient” or some accepted classical assumption (such as that exponentiation is well-defined). The motivation is either philosophical or for some application, such as to implementation of algorithms.Mints, to whom I am indebted for questioning me on this point, remarks that although there is a unique notion of computable function, there is not a unique notion of efficient computation or computability.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Cf. Gödel’s remark that the undecidability results “do not establish any bounds for the powers of human reason, but rather for the potentialities of pure formalism in mathematics.” (Postscriptum (1964) to “On undecidable propositions of formal mathematical systems,” Collected Works, volume I, Publications 1929–1936, Solomon Feferman et al, eds., p.370.)

    Google Scholar 

  37. “Infinity and Kant’s conception of the ‘possibility of experience’,” first published 1964, in Mathematics in Philosophy: Selected Essays (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  38. I do not deal at all with one possible objection to this proposed use of Turing: it is a matter of doubt and controversy whether the effective procedures called for by the intuitionistic understanding of the mathematical notion of function must be mechanical and thus whether Church’s thesis is an acceptable principle for intuitionistic mathematics. This question is clearly not relevant to the issues surrounding strict finitism.

    Google Scholar 

  39. See Petr Hájek and Pavel Pudlák, Metamathematics of First-Order Arithmetic (Springer-Verlag, 1993), ch. V, especially theorem 4.16, p.332.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1997 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Parsons, C. (1997). What Can We Do “In Principle”?. In: Dalla Chiara, M.L., Doets, K., Mundici, D., van Benthem, J. (eds) Logic and Scientific Methods. Synthese Library, vol 259. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0487-8_17

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0487-8_17

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4786-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-0487-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics