Skip to main content

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 47))

  • 151 Accesses

Abstract

When Spinoza writes in Chapter 16 of the Tractatus:

For it is certain that Nature, taken in the absolute sense, has the sovereign right to do all that she can do; that is, Nature’s right is co-extensive with her power [potentia]...it follows that each individual thing [unumquodque individuum] has the sovereign right to do all that it can do; i.e., the right of the individual [uniuscujusque eo] is co-extensive with its determinate power [potentia] (G3:189/S 179).1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. References to Spinoza’s works other than the Tractatus will be internal using the following standard abbreviations throughout: “PPC” for Principiaphilosophiae cartesianae; “CM” for Cogitata metaphysica; “E” for Ethica; “TTP” for Tractatus theologico-politicus; “TP” for Tractatus politicus; and “Ep” for Epistolae. Other standard abbreviations are p(-roposition), cor(-ollary), dem(-onstration), schol(-ium), def(-inition), and pref(-ace). E2p13cor would thus refer to the corollary to proposition 13 in the second part of the Ethica.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See, for example, E. Curley, “Kissinger, Spinoza, and Genghis Khan,”The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza, ed. D. Garrett ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996 ) p. 318.

    Google Scholar 

  3. A. Matheron, “Le `droit du plus fort’: Hobbes contre Spinoza,” Revue philosophique 110 (1985):176 [my translation].

    Google Scholar 

  4. C. Huenemann, “Teaching Spinoza’s Political Philosophy to Undergraduates,” delivered at the December 1996 meeting of the North American Spinoza Society (unpublished manuscript). Also see Matheron’s “Le `driot du plus fort’: Hobbes contre Spinoza,” p. 168.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Curley, “Kissinger, Spinoza, and Genghis Khan,” p. 335. 8P-F. Moreau,Spinoza( Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1975 ) p. 89.

    Google Scholar 

  6. E. Fernandez-García,“PotentiaetPostestasdans les premiers écrits de B. Spinoza,”Studia Spinozana4 (1988):195 [my translation]. Cf. R. McShea, “Spinoza on Power,”Inquiry12 (1969): 133.

    Google Scholar 

  7. A distinction between potentia and potestas has not escaped all commentators, yet no one has yet to offer an exhaustive analysis of these terms in Spinoza. A possible exception is Marin Terpstra’s De wending naar de politiek: Een studie over de begrippen potestas b# Spinoza, a dissertation submitted at Nijmegen in 1990. Two later publications by Terpstra seem to draw on conclusions reached in that earlier work. See his “An Analysis of Power Relations and Class Reactions in Spinoza’s Tractatus politicus,” Studia Spinozana 9 (1993):79–104

    Google Scholar 

  8. “What Does Spinoza Mean by `potentia multitudinis’?” eds. E. Balibar, H. Seidel, and M. Walther, Freiheit und Notwendigkeit: Ethische und politische Aspekte bei Spinoza und in der Geschichte des (Anti-)Spinozismus (Wurzburg: Königshausen and Neumann, 1994). Fernández-Garcia’s “Potentia et Potestas dans les premiers écrits de B. Spinoza” presents a very general overview of Spinoza’s use of these two terms in his earlier works.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. Chapter 2 of the TTP where Spinoza links summum jus to summa potentia (G3:39/S31). See also other passages at G3:38/S31; G3:193/S183; G3:201/S 191; G3:202/S192; and G3:206/S 195 for other examples of Spinoza’s joining right [jus] to power [potentia].

    Google Scholar 

  10. See A. Matheron, Individu et communauté chez Spinoza (Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1969) p. 22: “An individual [individu] is nothing other than the activity… in as much as this activity provides for it a determined structure”[my translation]. Cf. Matheron, “Spinoza et le problèmatique juridique de Grotius,” Philosophie 4 (1984):78.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. E4def8; E5p9dem; Ep64. Also, power is linked to desire [cupiditas] at G3:11/S7; G3:190/S180, and see where desire [cupiditas] is linked to essence: E3p9schol; E4def8.

    Google Scholar 

  12. This reading accords nicely with J. Bennett’s field metaphysic analogy, seeA Study of Spinoza’sEthics (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company,1984) pp. 91–106; and his “Spinoza’s Metaphysics,” inThe Cambridge Companion to Spinoza, pp. 63ff. Also compare M. Gueroult’s reading of a Spinozistic individual as a quantum of power inSpinoza II: l’âme(Paris: Aubier-Montaigne, 1974) p. 351; and C. Ramond’sQualité et quantité dans le philosophie de Spinoza(Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1995 ) pp. 222–28, 248–52.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Again, this seems to fit in well with Bennett’s field metaphysic analogy. Cf. where Spinoza writes about the potentia rerum naturalium, not the potentiae rerum naturialium (G3:461537; G3:81/S72) and later where he describes the potentia omnium individuorum rather than the potentiae omnium individuorum (G3:189/ S179). Actually, there is one passage wherein Spinoza writes about powers (in the plural) [duas itaque potentias], but here he is referring to the common people’s [vulgus] mistaken belief that God’s power is distinct from nature’s power (G3:81/ S72).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Spinoza does claim that some states may be stronger (potentius) than others (G3:196/S 186), but this does not necessarily mean that any state actually possesses power. Remember that he also claims that Jehovah is more powerful than other gods (G3:169/S 159), but this does not mean that any gods actually exist or have any power. Spinoza uses the term “potentius” two times in the TTP; it could be that “stronger” would be a better way to render “potentius.”

    Google Scholar 

  15. One is determined, then, to do what he/she judges to be most conducive to his/her own welfare. On this point see G. Belaief,Spinoza’s Philosophy of Law( The Hague: Mouton, 1971 ) p. 45

    Google Scholar 

  16. E.E. Harris, “Spinoza’s Treatment of Natural Law,”Spinoza ‘s Political and Theological Thought, ed. C. de Deugd ( Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company, 1984 ) pp. 65–67

    Google Scholar 

  17. L. Rice, “Emotions, Appetition, and Conatus in Spinoza,”Revue internationale de philosophie31 (1977): 110–114.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See, for example, R. McShea,The Political Philosophy of Spinoza( New York: Columbia University Press, 1968 ) pp. 156–176

    Google Scholar 

  19. L. Rice, “Spinoza and Highway Robbery,”Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie80 (1998): 95–102.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Indeed, see the heading for Chapter 17 (G3:201/S 191): “It is demonstrated that nobody can, or need, transfer all his rights to the sovereign power” [Ostenditur neminem omnia in Summam Potestatem transferre posse, nec esse necesse].

    Google Scholar 

  21. This reading of obligation has recently been called the “catch-me-ifyou-can” theory of obligation, see Rice, “Spinoza and Highway Robbery.” It has been argued that Spinoza himself exemplifies this in his preface and final chapter of the TTP wherein he says that if the civil authority finds anything objectionable in his book, he would change it (G3:12/S8; G3:247/S238). That a book already published makes this promise in effect says that if the authority could have stopped him, Spinoza would have not published it, but the authority did not stop him (and so de facto could not have stopped him), hence it really had no authority and so Spinoza was not held not to displease it.

    Google Scholar 

  22. So Spinoza writes to Willem van Blijenbergh that if one imagined that he would be better off hanging from a gallows than sitting at his own table, he would be a fool not to go hang himself [Ep23].

    Google Scholar 

  23. Again, see McShea’s The Political Philosophy ofSpinoza, pp. 156–176; and Rice’s “Spinoza and Highway Robbery.”

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Barbone, S. (1999). Power in the Tractatus theologico-politicus . In: Bagley, P.J. (eds) Piety, Peace, and the Freedom to Philosophize. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 47. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2672-6_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2672-6_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5326-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2672-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics