Skip to main content

Characterizing Referential Communication

  • Chapter
Success in Referential Communication

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 80))

  • 165 Accesses

Abstract

The present chapter attempts to provide a more detailed characterization of referring acts. In the first section I will expand further on the intuitive characterization of referring acts in terms of intentions to refer an audience to particular things one has in mind. Although this characterization allows us to draw certain important distinctions, as it stands it is quite imprecise since it rests on the vague notion of “having a thing in mind”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Reference

  1. This latter term is borrowed from Evans (1982). Although I think that his use of the term roughly corresponds to the use I make of the term here, there are some differences which will be pointed out in later chapters.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Essentially, what Evans calls the referential feature of an expression is what others have called its linguistic meaning or character.

    Google Scholar 

  3. It should be noted that Kripke refers to these kinds of reference as speaker reference and semantic reference respectively. Given the use I have made above of the term ‘speaker reference’ this terminology is quite misleading. For in both cases do uses of expressions by speakers figure as the bearers of reference, thus they both would classify as cases of speaker reference. In order to avoid terminological confusion I will stick to the terminology chosen above and continue to use the terms ‘intended reference’ and ‘conventional reference’.

    Google Scholar 

  4. It seems plausible that in claiming there is an object referred to in referring acts we first of all mean that there is an intended referent. For what one means by the words one uses seems more relevant to communication than what one says by them, as has been argued above.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See Searle (1969) for this latter classification.

    Google Scholar 

  6. What might be said against this is that whenever a name like ‘Frege’ gets rightly used one is performing a referring act. Yet what could it mean to say that one rightly uses a referring expression, if not that one uses it with the right kind of intention, that is with a referential intention?

    Google Scholar 

  7. The uses of these terms derive from Recanati (1993). As he spells it out “a term t is type referential if and only if its meaning includes a feature … by virtue of which it indicates that there is an object x such that an utterance of G(t) is true or more generally satisfied if and only if x satisfies G().”

    Google Scholar 

  8. The notion of a singular proposition was first introduced by Kaplan (1977). Such propositions are commonly conceived as ordered pairs of the form ‹R.‹o.o', …›› where R is a n-place relation and o, o', … a sequence of n particulars.

    Google Scholar 

  9. It should be remarked that Bach assumes here that the distinction is to be sought at the level of what is meant; on the level of what is said in both cases a uniqueness proposition gets expressed.

    Google Scholar 

  10. The best that can be said is that in referentially using a definite description the speaker intends to express a singular proposition; although it has to be added that this only holds for cases of discourse about reality. Yet the central problem then will be to make more precise what is meant by saying that someone intends to express a singular proposition, without actually expressing one. What kind of mental state is he in which differs from the one which underlies the attributive uses of definite descriptions?

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Paul, M. (1999). Characterizing Referential Communication. In: Success in Referential Communication. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 80. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3181-2_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3181-2_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5322-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3181-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics