Skip to main content

Atoms, Minds and Vortices in De Summa Rerum: Leibniz vis-à-vis Hobbes and Spinoza

  • Chapter
The Young Leibniz and his Philosophy (1646–76)

Abstract

The recent translation of De Summa Rerum by G. H. R. Parkinson has done much to revive speculation on the origins of Leibniz’s later metaphysics. Yet although De Summa Rerum is doubtless the most coherent body of Leibniz’s metaphysical writing between the Confessio Philosophi of 1671 and the Discourse of 1686, the thoughts expressed in it frequently seem to be related by dream logic rather than logic — there is a swirl of statements relating to minds, particles, God, and vortices which are highly resistant to systematic interpretation.1 Vortices, for example, are said to be associated with minds, with worlds, and with solid bodies. They do not reappear in such a field of associations, as far as I can determine, ever again: these vortices (unlike the mathematically describable ‘harmonic’ vortices, Leibniz preferred as a better fundamental explanation of planetary orbits than Newtonian gravitation) are true singularities in Leibniz’s theorising. In this paper I shall suggest that they are intended to function as solutions of what I will call the ‘contouring problem’, the problem of finding stable individuals, substances — as opposed to substance — in the spare ontology of the new philosophy. As Leibniz puts the question:

As the mind is something which has a certain relation to some portion of matter, then it must be stated why it extends itself to this portion and not to all adjacent portions; or, why it is that some body, and not every body, belongs to it in the same way.2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Reference

  1. For a previous approach to this problem, see G. H. R. Parkinson, `Leibniz’s De Summa Rerum: A Systematic Approach’, SL 18 (1986): 132–51.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Notes on Science and Metaphysics’, A VI iii 393: PDSR 45.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Whether Leibniz can be seen as a `Spinozist’ is a matter of emphasis, attribution, and relevant comparisons. If Leibniz’s focus on individuation is thought to be more important than his focus on perspectival harmony, he is not Spinozistic. If his references to creation by emanation are more properly described as Neo-platonic or as Scholastic, he is not Spinozistic. If the relevant contrast-class is given by Locke and Descartes, he is Spinozistic. Relevant discussions include Georges Friedmann, Leibniz et Spinoza, (2nd edition, Paris: Gallimard, 1962); Aaron Gurwitsch, Leibniz und den Panlogismus (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1974); Catherine Wilson, Leibniz’s Metaphysics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989), pp. 280–1, et passim: R. M. Adams, Leibniz: Determinist, Idealist,Theist (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1993), pp. 126–30; pp. 157 ff.; G. H. R. Parkinson, `Leibniz’s Paris Writings in relation to Spinoza’, SL Supp. 18 (1978): 73–91; Mark Kulstad, `Did Leibniz incline towards Monistic Pantheism in 1676?’, Leibniz und Europa. Proceedings of the Vlth International Leibniz-Kongress (Hanover, 1994), pp. 424–8, and `Leibniz’s De Summa Rerum: the Origin of the Variety of Things, in Connection with the Spinoza-Tschirnhaus Correspondence’, SL Sond. (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  4. L 196.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Leibniz, On Transubstantiation,’ in A VI i 509: L 116.

    Google Scholar 

  6. AVIi511:L118.

    Google Scholar 

  7. A VI i 512:L 119.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Marsilio Ficino, Opera I 531, quoted in Brian P. Copenhaver, `Astrology and Magic’, in The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy, ed. Quentin Skinner, Eckhard Kessler and Jill Kraye (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 264–301.

    Google Scholar 

  9. `On the Origin of Things from Forms’, PDSR 77; A VI iii 518.

    Google Scholar 

  10. TMark Kulstad, `Leibniz’s De Summa Rerum: the Origin of the Variety of Things’.

    Google Scholar 

  11. `That a Perfect Being is Possible’, in PDSR 93–5; A VI iii 573–4. Adams’ subtle gloss on this passage confirms that Leibniz could not fully accept an ontological distinction between the creator and the created and creation of the latter in orthodox fashion ex nihilo. Adams, Leibniz, p. 130–1. Cf. C. Wilson, Leibniz’s Metaphysics pp. 275–81.

    Google Scholar 

  12. `Notes on Science and Metaphysics’, A VI iii 391: PDSR 43.

    Google Scholar 

  13. I term a `perfection’ every simple quality which is positive and absolute, or, which expresses without any limits whatever it does express.“ (A VI iii 577: PDSR 99).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Notes on Science and Metaphysics’, A VI iii 392: PDSR 45.

    Google Scholar 

  15. ’A Most Perfect Being Exists’, A VI iii 572–3: PDSR 91–3.

    Google Scholar 

  16. On Leibniz and Hobbes, see Ferdinand Tönnies, ‘Leibniz und Hobbes’, in Studien zur Philosophie und Gesellschaftslehre im 17. Jahrhundert, ed. E. G. Jacoby (Stuttgart-Bad-Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 1975), 151–68; Konrad Moll, ‘Die erste Monadenkonzeption von Leibniz und ihr Ausgangspunkt in Conatus-Begriff und Perzeptionstheorie von Thomas Hobbes’, Proceedings of the Vth International Leibniz-Kongress, Hanover, 1988; H. M. Bernstein, ‘Conatus, Hobbes and the Young Leibniz’, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 11 (1980): 25–37; Jeffrey Barnouw, ‘The Separation of Reason and Faith in Bacon and Hobbes and Leibniz’s Theodicy’:,Journal of the History of Ideas 42 (1981): 607–28.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Preface to an Edition of Nizolius’, in L 124: G IV 143.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Letter to Herman Conring, L 189: G I 196–7.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Spragens, The Politics of Motion (Lexington, University Press of Kentucky, 1973), p. 73.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Thomas Hobbes, De Corpore in English Works ed. W. Molesworth (London: Bohn, 1939), De Corpore, Works,I 414.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., 1 426.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., 1 530.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., I 399.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., I 391–2.

    Google Scholar 

  25. There are living creatures so small we can scarcely see their whole bodies, “yet even these have their young ones; their little veins and other vessels, and their eyes so small as that no microscope can make them visible.” We cannot imagine any magnitude so small but that our very supposition is exceeded by nature. Ibid., I 446.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ethics, Pt. II, Prop. 17, Collected Works of Spinoza I 464.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ethics, Pt II, Prop. 12, Collected Works of Spinoza I 456.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ethics, Pt. II, Prop. 10, Collected Works of Spinoza I 454.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ethics, Pt II, Prop. 13, Axiom 3, Collected Works of Spinoza I 460.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ethics, Pt II, Prop. 13, Lemma 4, Cf. Lemma 7, Collected Works of Spinoza I 461.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ethics, Pt II, Prop. 13, Lemma 7, Collected Works of Spinoza I 461–2.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ethics, Pt. II, Prop. 11, Corollary, Collected Works of Spinoza 1 456.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ethics, Pt. II, Prop. 13, Collected Works of Spinoza I 457.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ethics, Pt. II, Prop. 13, Scholium, Collected Works of Spinoza I 458.

    Google Scholar 

  35. `On Truths, the Mind, God and the Universe’, A VI iii 510: PDSR 61.

    Google Scholar 

  36. `On the Union of Soul and Body’, A VI iii 480–1: PDSR 35–6.

    Google Scholar 

  37. `On the Origin of Things from Forms’, A VI iii 519: PDSR 77.

    Google Scholar 

  38. `On the Plenitude of the World’, A VI iii 524: PDSR 85.

    Google Scholar 

  39. `On the Union of Soul and Body’, A VI iii 480–1: PDSR 35–6.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Leibniz, Hypothesis physica nova, A V ii 223.

    Google Scholar 

  41. `On the Plenitude of the World’, A VI iii 525: PDSR 89.

    Google Scholar 

  42. `On the Secrets of the Sublime’, A VI iii 476–7: PDSR 31.

    Google Scholar 

  43. `On Truths, the Mind, God, and the Universe’, A VI iii 509–10: PDSR 61.

    Google Scholar 

  44. `On the Union of Soul and Body’, A VI iii 480: PDSR 35.

    Google Scholar 

  45. `Excerpts from Notes on Science and Metaphysics’, A VI iii 393: PDSR 47.

    Google Scholar 

  46. `On the Secrets of the Sublime’, A VI iii 474: PDSR 25.

    Google Scholar 

  47. `On the Union of Soul and Body’, A VI iii 480: PDSR 37.

    Google Scholar 

  48. `On the Plenitude of the World’, A VI iii 525: PDSR 87.

    Google Scholar 

  49. `On the Origin of Things from Forms’, A VI iii 521: PDSR 81.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Thomas Hobbes, Thomas White’s De Mundo Examined, trans. H. W. Jones (London: Bradford University Press, 1976), p. 254.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Ethics Pt II, Prop. 13 Axiom 3, Lemma 4, Collected Works of Spinoza I 460–1.

    Google Scholar 

  52. `On the Secrets of the Sublime’, A VI iii 474–5: PDSR 27.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  54. `On the Origin of Things from Forms’, A VI iii 518: PDSR 75.

    Google Scholar 

  55. `On Truths, the Mind, God, and the Universe’, PDSR 61: A VI iii 510.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Ibid., A VI iii 510: PDSR 63.

    Google Scholar 

  57. J. T. Barnouw, ‘Hobbes’s Psychology of Thought’, History of European Ideas 10 (1989): 519–45.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Ethics, Pt. IV, Props. XX-XXV: Collected Works of Spinoza I 557–9.

    Google Scholar 

  59. This image can properly be regarded both as a prefiguring of the doctrine of `world-apart’ monads and of the Theodicy’s influential theory of creative activity as the artist’s imitation of divine creation.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wilson, C. (1999). Atoms, Minds and Vortices in De Summa Rerum: Leibniz vis-à-vis Hobbes and Spinoza. In: Brown, S. (eds) The Young Leibniz and his Philosophy (1646–76). International Archives of the History of Ideas / Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Idées, vol 166. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3507-0_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3507-0_11

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5332-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3507-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics