Skip to main content

On Biological Explanations

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy of Cancer

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 18))

  • 537 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter I outline some aspects that characterize biological explanations when the explananda are “functionalities”, ongoing dynamics. This sketch of a theory of explanation is tightly linked with the notion of Operational Integrating Systems, and, more generally, with all the dimensions of the Dynamic and Relational View of cancer explored in Chap. 5. We will deal with a fundamental epistemological duality constituted by, on one hand, the identification of the explanatory level according to our research interest and, on the other hand, the characterization of the system’s dynamisms we want to study. We will introduce the idea of “mesosystem” (between micro and macro) and its derivatives, arguing that reduction operates by “mesoscopic reasoning”, seeking the right explanatory level for the dynamic that needs to be understood. We will use the mesoscopic concept to reflect on why all cancer research seems to be converging on the tissue level and to derive some criteria for choosing a particular explanatory level in scientific practice. Reduction is thus methodologically adopted but it is constrained by validity conditions that are directly determined by the relational nature of the studied systems, whose elements are functionally defined by the higher level properties and ontologically dependent on them too. This is also why anti-reductionist views can play the role of defining the systems and the contexts, while reductionist views can’t. We will also deepen the crucial notions of “stability” and “specificity”, “determination” and “indetermination”. The two pairs of terms are fundamental to appreciate how our theory of explanation is deeply entangled with the operational nature of biological dynamisms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The roots of this concept is found in the field of Systems Biology and of the methodological considerations presented by Noble (2006).

  2. 2.

    Relevant considerations with respect to this issue have been also presented in Buzzoni (2015).

  3. 3.

    This opens a philosophical reflection about the correspondence between the world and the way we know it through science. A compositional and pluralistic view of the scientific enterprise is better suited to explain why and how science works, but the philosophical implication of what is a common practice in science does not seem to be at hand yet.

  4. 4.

    Moreover, describing functional dynamics that are nomologically dependent on the context through models, where those dynamics are reconstructed in mechanistic terms, allows us to make machines able to perform those functional properties through parts and devices that act in a mechanistic way. As noted by Agazzi, this possibility does not imply equivalence between living and non-living systems. The latter remain nevertheless ‘artificial’ because they are not able to undergo all the reciprocal relations in which natural organs are usually involved (Agazzi 1978).

  5. 5.

    In this way, Schaffner makes explicit his original concern about the nature of theory in biology: while incorporating mechanistic explanations in his CM approach, he still takes into account the possibility that the real nature of biological theories might have been originally misconceived, avoiding the discussion of their nomological character or resolving it in mechanistic terms.

  6. 6.

    As Schaffner does in his paper (2006), I will also consider this point in its epistemological dimension. Logic and ontological discussion are also required and already developed, at least partially, elsewhere (Mitchell 2010; Bertolaso 2013a, b) but are beyond the aim of the present volume.

  7. 7.

    In the same article (2012), Schaffner is moving from coupling the term of “creeping” with “reductionism” to coupling it with “reductions”. The reason is the difference he makes with sweeping reductionism and the focus on the plurality of potential “creeping reductions” that can be performed and are exemplified in his paper. I adopt this useful distinction.

  8. 8.

    On this point some considerations about the kind of “information” that is required in Schaffner’s definition of strong emergence can be developed: “all the information about the parts and the connections will never allow an explanation of the whole” (Schaffner 2006, p. 383) along with a discussion of the caveat about interrelations among parts included in the last part of the definition of “innocuous emergence” (ibidem, pp. 382–3).

  9. 9.

    On this point see also footnote n. 10 of Chap. 5 and the relevance of the structure of molecular biology experiments.

  10. 10.

    On this point of particular interest is the work done by Capp (2005). Special attention has been also devoted to the demonstration that genetic instability itself (therefore, the accumulation of mutations) follows the onset of an abnormal microenvironment, as studies seem to demonstrate the genetic instability of stem cells, when grown without control of the microenvironment (Maitra et al. 2005). The same could happen in pre-malignant cells, after the loss of the stabilizing effects from the organization of surrounding tissue. The subsequent deregulation of the DNA maintenance pathways, generated by alteration of the microenvironment, would be sufficient to generate the defects observed in cancer cells, so mutations that inactivate specific genes involved in cell differentiation may be, more generally, a consequence of the other non-mutational mechanisms, prompting the remark (already found in Chap. 1 regarding cell differentiation) that, “It may be more correct to say that cancers beget mutations than it is to say that mutations beget cancers” (Prehn 1994). Here, however, I focus on the context-dependence of the effect of mutations (i.e., specificity) once they had occurred.

  11. 11.

    On this point cfr. also the analysis offered in Bertolaso 2009a, b of cell-centred and systemic account of the hallmarks of cancer.

  12. 12.

    Despite the wide-ranging debate on the question of determinism, in this study we refer to this concept only for those elements that can provide better understanding of the philosophical doctrines dominating also scientific research programs in the last century. No deterministic doctrine is a consequence only of the observation of phenomena, it is also, and above all, the result of a number of conceptual assumptions (Ferrater Mora 1994) that are not indifferent in scientific practice.

  13. 13.

    The topic would have to be looked into in greater depth and from a broader perspective considering how, through analogous mechanisms, living systems can evolve and structure their “knowledge” of their functional state (phenotypic identity) and their environment. This would also be necessary in order to understand better how the informational dimension, contained in the genes, and that which pertains to the biological context, relate to one another. This point goes beyond the objectives that we have proposed here. It is a topic that is open to reflection concerning the peculiarity of the growth and development of living organisms.

  14. 14.

    Such difference, that is crucial from an experimental point of view, can be further clarified analyzing different kinds of noise in biological sciences and how they are treated (cf. Bertolaso et al. 2013). It is interesting how this point meets the concern about the limitedness of the natural selection argument made by Vineis et al. (2010, cf. Section 2.8).

References

  • Agazzi, E. (1978). Systems theory and the problem of reductionism. Erkenntnis, 12, 339–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, S. G., Soto, A. M., Sonnenschein, C., Capuccino, A., Potter, J. D., & Kramer, B. S. (2009). Plausibility of stromal initiation of epithelial cancers without a mutation in the epithelium: A computer simulation of morphostats. BMC Cancer, 9, 89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertolaso, M. (2009a). The neoplastic process and the problems with the attribution of function. Rivista di Biologia/Biology Forum, 102, 273–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertolaso, M. (2009b). Towards an integrated view of the neoplastic phenomena in cancer research. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciencies, 31, 79–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertolaso, M. (2013a). How science works: Choosing levels of explanation in biological sciences. Roma: Aracne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertolaso, M. (2013b). On the structure of biological explanations: Beyond functional ascriptions in cancer research. Epistemologia, 36, 112–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertolaso, M. (2013c). Mechanisms & biological mechanisms. In New Catholic encyclopedia supplement 2012–2013: Ethics and philosophy. Detroit: Robert L. Fastiggi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertolaso M. (2013d). Indeterminación Biológica y las Perspectivas Sistémicas de la Biología Contemporáne – Biological Uncertainty and the Systemic Perspectives of Contemporary Biology. Anuario Filosofico, 46, 365–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertolaso M. (2013e). Sulla ‘irriducibilità’ della prospettiva sistemica in biologia. Un’analisi delle convergenze dei modelli interpretativi del cancro. In L. Urbani Ulivi (Ed.), Strutture di Mondo (Vol. II, pp. 143–169). Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertolaso, M., Giuliani, A., & Filippi, S. (2013). The mesoscopic level and its epistemological relevance in systems biology. In Recent advances in systems biology (Vol. 1, pp. 1–18). New York: Nova Science Publishers, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bizzarri, M., Giuliani, A., Cucina, A., D’Anselmi, F., Soto, A. M., & Sonnenschein, C. (2011). Fractal analysis in a systems biology approach to cancer. Seminars in Cancer Biology, 21, 175–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1979). Causality and modern science (Vol. 7). New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni, M. (2015). Causality, teleology, and thought experiments in biology. Journal of General Philosophy of Science, 46, 279–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capp, J. P. (2005). Stochastic gene expression, disruption of tissue averaging effects, and cancer as a disease of development. Bioessays, 27, 1277–1285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, A. P., Ohlsson, R., & Henikoff, S. (2006). The epigenetic progenitor origin of human cancer. Nature Reviews Genetics, 7, 21–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferrater, M. J. (1994). Diccionario de Filiosofia. Bercelona: Ariel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giuliani, A. (2010). Collective motions and specific effectors: A statistical mechanics perspective on biological regulation. BMC Genomics, 11(Suppl 1), S2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, H. (2005). A long view of fashions in cancer research. BioEssays: News and Reviews in Molecular, Cellular and Developmental Biology, 27(8), 833–838.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heng, H. H., Bremer, S. W., Stevens, J., Ye, K. J., Miller, F., Liu, G., & Ye, C. J. (2006a). Cancer progression by non-clonal chromosome aberrations. Journal of Cellular Biochemistry, 98, 1424–1435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hochedlinger, K., Blelloch, R., Brennan, C., Yamada, Y., Kim, M., Chin, L., & Jaenisch, R. (2004). Reprogramming of a melanoma genome by nuclear transplantation. Genes & Development, 18, 1875–1885.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, A., et al. (2002). Serum tryptophan decrease correlates with immune activation and impaired quality of life in colorectal cancer. British Journal of Cancer, 86(11), 1691–1696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaffe, L. (2005). Response to paper by Henry Harris. Bioessays, 27, 1206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, P. A., & Bissell, M. J. (2003). Tumor reversion: Correction of malignant behaviour by microenvironmental cues. International Journal of Cancer, 107, 688–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2000). Causation as influence. The Journal of Philosophy, 47, 182–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lotem, J., & Sachs, L. (2002). Epigenetics wins over genetics: Induction of differentiation in tumor cells. Seminars in Cancer Biology, 12, 339–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maitra, A., Arking, D. E., Shivapurkar, N., Ikeda, M., Stastny, V., Kassauei, K., Sui, G., Cutler, D. J., Liu, Y., Brimble, S. N., Noaksson, K., Hyllner, J., Schulz, T. C., Zeng, X., Freed, W. J., Crook, J., Abraham, S., Colman, A., Sartipy, P., Matsui, S. I., Carpenter, M., Gazdar, A. F., Rao, M., & Chakravarti, A. (2005). Genomic alterations in cultured human embryonic stem cells. Nature Genetics, 37, 1099–1103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martien, S., & Abbadie, C. (2007). Acquisition of oxidative DNA damage during senescence: The first step toward carcinogenesis? Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1119, 51–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLauglin, P. (2001). What functions explain. Functional explanation and self-reproducing systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mintz, B., & Illmensee, K. (1975). Normal genetically mosaic mice produced from malignant teratocarcinoma cells. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 72, 3585–3589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. D. (2000). Dimensions of scientific law. Philosophy of Science, 67, 242–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. D. (2008). Explaining complex behavior. In K. S. Kendler & J. Parnas (Eds.), Philosophical issues in psychiatry: Explanation, phenomenology, and nosology (pp. 19–38). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noble, D. (2006). The music of life: Biology beyond the genome. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palumbo, M. C., et al. (2005). Functional essentiality from topology features in metabolic networks: A case study in yeast. FEBS Letters, 579(21), 4642–4646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palumbo, M. C., et al. (2007). Essentiality is an emergent property of metabolic network wiring. FEBS Letters, 581(13), 2485–2489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prehn, R. T. (1994). Cancers beget mutations versus mutations beget cancers. Cancer Res, 54, 5296–300. (Cfr. Van Speybroeck, L. (2002). From epigenesist to epigenetics: The case of CH Waddington. Annals of New York Academic Science, 981: 61–81).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruddon, R. W. (1995). Cancer biology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. F. (1993). Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. F. (2002). Neuroethics: Reductionism, emergence, and decision-making capacities. In S. J. Marcus (Ed.), Neuroethics: Mapping the field (pp. 27–33). New York: The Dana Foundation Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. F. (2006). Reduction: The Cheshire Cat problem and a return to roots. Synthese, 151, 377–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. F. (2013a). Behaving. What’s genetic and what’s not and why should we care? Monograph. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. F. (2016). Behaving: What’s genetic, what’s not, and why should we care? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Soto, A. M., & Sonnenschein, C. (2004). The somatic mutation theory of cancer: Growing problems with the paradigm? BioEssays, 26, 1097–1107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vineis, P., Schatzkin, A., & Potter, J. D. (2010). Models of carcinogenesis: An overview. Carcinogenesis, 31, 1703–1709.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C. H. (1977). Tools for thought (p. 145). London: Jonathan Cape Thirty Bedford Square.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2006). Sensitive and insensitive causation. The Philosophical Review, 115, 1–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2010). Causation in biology: Stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 25, 287–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1992). Mental causation. Philosophical Review, 101, 245–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bertolaso, M. (2016). On Biological Explanations. In: Philosophy of Cancer. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 18. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-0865-2_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics