Skip to main content

Types of Conversational Backgrounds and Arguments

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Modality in Argumentation

Part of the book series: Argumentation Library ((ARGA,volume 29))

  • 394 Accesses

Abstract

The chapter reconstructs the most relevant “flavors” of modality (alethic , deontic , deontic-practical , anankastic, and epistemic) in terms of a relational , discourse sensitive, context dependent , procedural approach to the interpretation of modal constructions . The approach, while inspired by Relative Modality and the formal semantics tradition, integrates pragmatic insights and it is cast as a tool for the actual analysis of discourse and argumentation . This approach to the typology of modal “flavors” is needed because the full indicative potential of a modal emerges only when its conversational background has been specified. At this point, the modal will act as a guide in the clarification of argumentative confrontations, in the specification of the logical type of the standpoint , in the recovery of premises as well as in the determination of the inferential structure of the argument (argumentation scheme ), where the flavor of modality can help by suggesting the locus-relation invoked by the argumentation scheme. The semantic category of evidentiality , which is closely related to epistemic modality , is also briefly examined in relation to argumentation , with a survey of the most basic categories of evidence sources encoded by languages (perception, testimony, inference ).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Here, as in the rest of the chapter, I use construction in a technical sense, albeit not far from the ordinary one, which comes from the theoretical trend of construction grammars , initiated by Charles J. Fillmore and Paul Kay (cf. Kay 2004, Kay and Michaelis 2008). In construction grammars a construction is “a form-meaning pair such that some aspect of its form or some aspect of its meaning is not strictly predictable from its component parts or from other constructions ” (cf. Goldberg 1995: 11). Constructions can specify syntactic slots as well as a part of the lexical and morphological filling of said slots and conventionally associate them with semantic constraints at the level of the propositional content, illocutionary force and discourse function of the utterance. Specific construction inherit formal and semantic features from the lexical and morphological material they embed as well as from more abstract syntactic templates, but also feature further specifications that are conventionally associated to the whole.

  2. 2.

    As we will see in Chap. 6, this strategy is frequent in the corpus of Italian business and financial news reporting on which the analyses of Italian modals in Chap. 6 are based. The Italian example in (4) is, in fact, taken from that corpus.

  3. 3.

    See example (65) in Chap. 4.

  4. 4.

    In contrast, see Groefsema (1995) for an attempt at explaining the interpretations of the English modals with a sketchy context dependent semantics – broadly inspired by Kratzer – enriched by contextual inferences , without any recourses to broad classes of modal interpretation. In Rocci (2005a: 208–2011) I make some critical observation on the viability of this attempt. Partly similar observations can be found in Papafragou (2000).

  5. 5.

    I mean empirical as opposed to the conceptually necessary aspects of human cognitive functioning.

  6. 6.

    As it often happens for modern syntactic terminology, the terms raising and control are based on transformational metaphors rooted in early Generative Grammar. This makes them relatively opaque. In non-transformational terms (cf. Fried and Östman 2004: 63–66), raising and control structures are both constructions characterized by the co-instantiation of the subject of the non-finite verbal complement (e.g. the infinitival) and the subject of the main predicate (the modal verb in our case). The two constructions differs in that control main predicates (e.g. try) assign a semantic argumentS slot to their subjects, while raising predicates (e.g. seem) do not. While filling the syntactic role of subject also in the main predicate, in raising structures the co-instantiated subject is semantically tied only to the infinitival complement.

  7. 7.

    Portner (2009: 188) proposes a nuanced position according to which “some deontic modals are control predicates and some are raising predicates”. For the purposes of the present investigation it is not necessary to enter this debate. Note that, in the perspective of Congruity Theory arguments can be recognized on semantic grounds irrespectively of the systematicity of their syntactic manifestation, and notions such as agent or deontic subject arguments remain important to understand certain flavors of modality even if they are only sporadically mapped ont complements.

  8. 8.

    Note that force dynamic theory of Talmy (1985) and Sweetser (1990) has (had?) the ambition not only to offer a solution to the problem of the poly-functionality of modal expressions, but also, to offer a general semantic account of the underlying notional categories alternative to the logico-semantic treatments in terms of possible worlds. A discussion of the merits of the approach exceeds the concerns of this book, but see Rocci (2005a: 151–169) and Portner (2009: 110–115) for a critique.

  9. 9.

    Examples adapted from Knott (2001: 129).

  10. 10.

    See Chap. 4, Def. 12 in § 4.2.7.1.

  11. 11.

    In principle, a similar, but not identical, distinction between alethic and non-alethic conversational backgrounds operates also within the epistemic conversational backgrounds separating the properly epistemic conversational backgrounds understood as selecting the set of known facts and the merely doxastic ones, comprising sets of beliefs which “may bear”, as Papafragou (2000: 70) puts it, “a variable degree of correspondence to the actual world”.

  12. 12.

    Cf. Kronning (1996: 70) “qui sont vraies en vertu de leur sens indépendamment de toute verification émpirique”.

  13. 13.

    See for instance Nuyts (2006: 8–9) and the one footnote devoted to the issue by Portner (2009: 135).

  14. 14.

    For a dispositional modal analysis of the French and Italian future tense see also Ludlow (1999) and Rocci (2000).

  15. 15.

    This does not preclude that, by stipulating a null contract, the parties might have thereby violated some deontic obligation. For instance, if they knowingly did so in order to commit a fraud or if there was negligence on their part in ascertaining that the conditions of validity subsist.

  16. 16.

    They are a good reminder of the fact that not only the peculiarities of each language – where central modal words may have restrictions that inhibit certain conversational backgrounds – but also the entrenched traditions of exemplification and grammatical description, can create blind spots in the most astute analysts. Ordinary language philosophers were sometimes criticized for being dilettante lexicographers, all too prone to see important philosophical distinctions under the patterns created by English idioms. I believe this criticism to be partly unwarranted. It may have merit as long as it concerns the linguistic dilettantism sometimes displayed by ordinary language philosophers, but not as regards the philosophical interest of linguistic analyses. The proper description of semantic distinctions enshrined by linguistic conventions regularly raises fundamental and difficult questions about the categories we use in reasoning . “Idioms” can be illuminating, provided that they are systematically analyzed with the right tools. That said, the “idioms” of other languages do not have a lesser status and should not be dismissed as something only descriptive linguists should care about. As we close towards the Italian language case studies of Chap. 6, I hope the reader will appreciate them for what they tell us about the nature of modality in connection with the essential structure of arguments .

  17. 17.

    On quantificational modals see also Chap. 4, § 4.3.3, which explores their indirect indicative power in the determination of argumentation structure .

  18. 18.

    Cf. Chap. 3, § 3.2.3.

  19. 19.

    Here I remain agnostic as to the syntactic, semantic , pragmatic or simply cognitive nature of this stratification. Where these scope issues are dealt with is a highly theory-dependent issue exceeding the boundaries of the present work.

  20. 20.

    This Italian example is taken from from the corpus of Italian business and financial news that I have exploited for the case studies expounded in Chap. 6.

  21. 21.

    Actually, Hacquard (2011: 1508) believes that for tense the situation is more clear-cut: “epistemics cannot scope under tense”. This may be correct for English, but the data about Italian modal verbs examined in Rocci (2005a: 256–259) suggest that the necessity modal dovere and the possibility modal potere behave differently with respect to tense and the interpretation of epistemic potere under the scope of tense, while impossible with most tenses, seems to be possible with the imperfect tense (cf. Rocci 2005: 258).

  22. 22.

    Leaving aside, here, does not imply a negative evaluation . Simply, the investigation syntax-semantics interface lays beyond the confines of the present study and a discussion of Hacquard’s implementation of event relativity in term of syntactic binding of the modal ’s event variable will be out of place.

  23. 23.

    Note that in (Def. 2) this notion is expressed using the possible worlds semantics and ontology adopted by the theory of Relative Modality , saying that w belongs to the inter of the set of propositions selected by the conversational background function f for w. As observed in Chap. 4, § 4.2.7.1, since a proposition is a set of possible worlds (the set of worlds the proposition is true at), the set of propositions f(w) can immediately be translated in to a set of worlds ∩f(w), corresponding the inter of all the propositions (i.e. sets of worlds) in f(w). Thus, saying that the inter of f(w) includes w is equivalent to saying that every proposition of f(w) is true at w. These idioms of possible worlds semantics may well seem counterintuitive to readers unfamiliar with the formal semantic tradition. Possible worlds provide a powerful framework for semantics, but there is a price to pay, as well as certain limitations, which will become more apparent in the fine grained linguistic semantic analyses of Chap. 6. To the reader perplexed by possible worlds semantics, it is perhaps worth reminding that, as observed by Kratzer herself, the key ideas of Relative Modality , are not tied to a possible worlds ontology and “can be implemented in any framework that provides suitable notions of logical consequence and compatibility” (Kratzer 2012 [1977]: 10, see Chap. 4, § 4.2.7.1 above).

  24. 24.

    See the Introduction at § 1.6.1 and Chap. 3, § 3.4.2.3for more references about the Medieval discussion on modalities in which Scotus’ distinction originates.

  25. 25.

    In Hacquard’s (2010, 2011) original contribution, event relativity is presented chiefly as a hypothesis on the syntax-semantics interface, while the procedural variant presented here frames it as a hypothesis on the interaction between linguistic semantics and discourse interpretation, analogous to procedural models of tense. One can imagine that a comprehensive formulation integrating these two aspects is possible. In every case, it remains a linguistic-semantic , rather than logico-semantic, endeavor.

  26. 26.

    The view of alethic modalities expressed here goes against the view aired by Papafragou (2000) and by others that the so-called “alethic modalities ” are, in fact, a variant of epistemic interpretations.

  27. 27.

    Both frameworks have been presented in Chap. 2, respectively in § 2.3.3 and § 2.2.3.

  28. 28.

    Admittedly, putting side by side Relative Modality – a very abstract but also formally precise semantic theory – with AMT – a framework for the study of argumentative inferences adopting a richer ontology, but still lacking proper formalization and a semantics – may seem an exercise in futility. It is important to stress, though, that what is mapped onto AMT here is not the possible world implementation of Relative Modality , but just the key idea of a premise semantics based on notions of logical consequence and compatibility.

  29. 29.

    The comparison cannot be drawn beyond a certain point, though. Institutional and natural alethic modalities are alike in their respect of Axiom T. There are, however, crucial differences connected with the ontological specificities of institutional facts In brief, while changes in physical circumstantial alethic modalities originate in physical causality, changes in institutional alethic modalities originate from a renegotiation of a collective assignment of status function (cf. Searle 2005: 7–10), in our example the status function that “Such and such a set of procedures counts as the election of a president of the United States” (Searle 2005: 7).

  30. 30.

    The format for semantic representation of Congruity Theory and its presuppositional analysis of selectional restrictions that predicates impose on their argument places have been introduced in Chap. 2, § 2.3.4.

  31. 31.

    Nor I will discuss finer, but philosophically important, distinctions among different types of teleological ethics such as eudaimonism vs. utilitarianism. In his Guildford Lectures von Wright (1963b) contrasts the teleological views of moral norms with prescriptivist views (moral norms are akin to commands) and deontological views (moral norms are entirely sui generis and do not need to be brought back to a source or justification).

  32. 32.

    In this respect Kronning’s view on nomic regularities differs from Freeman’s. Freeman (2005) does not use the notion of nomic regularity in his treatment of evaluations .

  33. 33.

    I translate from the French original: “ces régularités nomiques sont donc, elles-mêmes, le produit d’une composition inférentielle” (Kronning 1996: 36).

  34. 34.

    While I adopt here the term thetic, which Carmello (2009) derives from philosophers of law, such as Amedeo G. Conte, the view of the landscape of deontic modality espoused by Carmello’s chapter could not be farther from the one defended here. For Carmello theticity is the very essence of deontic modality , which covers just performative thetic statements and their reports. On the (presumable) thetic origin of moral norms nothing is said.

  35. 35.

    According to a widespread hypothesis in formal linguistic studies of discourse , attachment relations between discourse sequences are subject to the right frontier constraint (Asher and Lascarides 2003): a discourse sequence can “attach” only to sequences that are either adjacent to it or to sequences that dominate hierarchically over those adjacent to it. These sequences are said to be on the right frontier. Attachment to sequences deeply buried down and left in the discourse is presumed to be impossible. While the right frontier constraint has a certain predictive power in calculating some attachment phenomena – e.g. the functioning of structural discourse connectives (cf. Chap. 4, § 4.3.6.2, and see Forbes-Riley et al. 2005)– there are also more indirect and inference -driven forms of anaphoric recovery that can circumvent it, and pick-up virtually any discourse meaning, making it the object of reprise. Anaphoric connectives in the sense of Forbes-Riley et al. (2005), and modals even more so can function in this manner. To these phenomena, I refer generically with the term resumption.

  36. 36.

    I note in passing that accepting that the conditional antecedent if America is to be a great nation contributes to the evaluative – i.e. properly deontic – part of the conversational background would not be obvious from the viewpoint of Kratzer’s original version of Relative Modality , where if-clauses contribute propositions that are added to the modal base f(w). The problem is that in the original theory (cf. Kratzer 1991: 649, Portner 2009: 72) deontic conversational backgrounds are supposed to only contribute ordering sources g(w). The semantics of a deontic reading of a modal like must is obtained through a modal base f(w) of factual circumstances selecting a set of worlds which is then ordered thanks to the norms in the deontic ordering source . As a consequence, the theory fits well if-clauses that modify the circumstantial base of the deontic (e.g. If you arrive late, you must wait outside) but does not allow for if-clauses contributing to the properly normative , bouletic or teleological part of the conversational background – as (114) seems to do – because conditional antecedents are not added to ordering sources.

  37. 37.

    By deontic subject I mean the person – physical or juridical – who is under the obligation to act or has the faculty to act.

  38. 38.

    The World Game, June, 9, 2006. Retrieved August 15, 2006 from http://www6.sbs.com.au/socceroos/index.php?pid=st&cid=71987

  39. 39.

    It has to be observed, though, that a view of deontic-practical possibility as mere compatibility with reaching the goal is not adequate. Examples such as To reach the summit of Monte Brè you can eat tomato salad or To prepare a good coffee you can wear pink underwear strike us as nonsensical even if eating tomato salad does not prevent us from reaching the summit and the color of underwear is not negatively affecting our ability to prepare coffee. Should we conclude that deontic-practical possibility modals indicate sufficient conditions for attaining the goal? Actually, a sufficiency presupposition would be too strong. In ordinary causal interpretations, as observed by Freeman (2005: 144), causes are hardly sufficient conditions. When I say The match lit because it was struck I presuppose (or “presume” as Freeman says) a host of out of focus necessary conditions (a force of sufficient magnitude, the presence of oxygen, the match being dry). A fully fledged account of deontic-practical can would require this predicate to have a presupposition of sufficiency given a conversational background of normal conditions. Such a presumptive sufficiency operator would be a special kind of necessity operator.

  40. 40.

    If these preferences fail to make a difference we enter a “Buridan’s ass” type of situation.

  41. 41.

    This set of dialectical rules can be conceived either as an ideal model – like the Pragma-Dialectical model of the critical discussion – or as a set of institutionalized argumentatively relevant conventions that hold in a given argumentative activity type, like, for instance, an adjudication in court (Cf. van Eemeren 2010, Chap. 6). This gives rise to two distinct flavors of meta-argumentative possibility : something may well be at the same time a possible standpoint to defend in a critical discussion and an impossible case to bring to court in view of the procedural constraints of the relevant judicial system.

  42. 42.

    The nature of epistemic modality in ordinary language and the path through which epistemic interpretations of context -dependent modals are obtained have already been discussed at some length in this chapter (§ 5.2.4), as well as in Chap. 33.3.3, in particular). Here, I take stock of what has emerged in the previous s and prepare the terrain for Chap. 6, which will delve deeper into the argumentative properties of epistemic readings of specific modal constructions in Italian.

  43. 43.

    The problem of logical omniscience affecting epistemic and doxastic logics interpreted via a possible worlds semantics arises because under these logics knowers know all the logical consequences of their knowledge. Whether this obviously unrealistic feature truly is a problem or an acceptable idealization depends very much on the intended applications of the logic.

  44. 44.

    The expertise variant of the locus from authority remains marginally possible.

References

  • Aikhenvald A (2007) Information source and evidentiality: what can we conclude? Rivista di Linguistica (Special Issue on Evidentiality between Lexicon and Grammar) 19(1):207–227

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher N, Lascarides A (2003) Logics of conversation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bybee J, Perkins R, Pagliuca W (1994) The evolution of grammar: tense, aspect and modality in the languages of the world. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Carmello M (2009) Considerazioni semantiche e pragmatiche sull’anankastico. A partire Da Maria-Elisabeth Conte. In: Venier F (ed) Tra pragmatica e linguistica testuale. Ricordando Maria-Elisabeth Conte. Edizioni dell’Orso, Alessandria, pp 205–235

    Google Scholar 

  • Cinque G (1999) Adverbs and functional heads: a cross-linguistic perspective. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Conte M-E (2010[1995]) Epistemico, deontico, anankastico. In Venier F, Proietti D (eds) Vettori del testo. Carocci, Roma, pp 151–159 (Originally published in From pragmatics to syntax. Modality in second language acquisition, eds. Anna Giacalone Ramat and Grazia Crocco Galèas, 3–9. Tübingen: Gunter Narr)

    Google Scholar 

  • de Haan F (2006) Typological approaches to modality. In: Frawley W (ed) The expression of modality. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin/New York, pp 27–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Dendale P (1994) Devoir épistémique, marqueur modal ou évidentiel? Langue française 102(1):24–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Saussure L (2003) Temps et pertinence. De Boeck – Duculot, Bruxelles

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Faller MT (2002) Semantics and pragmatics of evidentials in Cuzco Quechua. Stanford University, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Faller MT (2011) A possible worlds semantics for Cuzco Quechua Evidentials. In: Li N, Lutz D (eds) Proceedings of SALT 20. CLC Publications, Ithaca, pp 660–683

    Google Scholar 

  • Forbes-Riley K, Webber B, Joshi A (2005) Computing discourse semantics: the predicate-argument semantics of discourse connectives in D-LTAG. J Semant 23:55–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman JB (2000) What type of statements are there? Argumentation 14(2):135–157

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman JB (2005) Acceptable premises: an epistemic approach to an informal logic problem. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman JB (2011) Argument structure: representation and theory. Springer, Amsterdam

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fried M, Östman J-O (2004) Construction grammar. a thumbnail sketch. In: Fried M, Ostman J-O (eds) Construction Grammar in a cross-language perspective. John Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia, pp 11–87

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Geurts B (1999) Presuppositions and pronouns. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert M (2013) Joint commitment. How we make the social world. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Givón T (1982) Evidentiality and epistemic space. Stud Lang 6(1):23–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg AE (1995) Constructions: a construction grammar approach to argument structure. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice HP (1989) Studies in the ways of words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Groefsema M (1995) Can, may, must and should: a relevance theoretic account. J Linguist 31:53–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacquard V (2010) On the event relativity of modal auxiliaries. Nat Lang Semant 18(1):79–114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacquard V (2011) Modality. In: Von Heusinger M, Portner P (eds) Semantics (HSK 33.2). Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin/New York, pp 1484–1515

    Google Scholar 

  • Hengeveld K (1988) Illocution, mood and modality in a functional grammar of Spanish. J Semant 6:227–269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jespersen O (1924) The philosophy of grammar. Allen & Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen L (1972) Possible and must. In: Kimball J (ed) Syntax and semantics, vol 1. Academic, New York, pp 1–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann S, Condoravdi C, Harizanov V (2006) Formal approaches to modality. In: Frawley W (ed) The expression of modality. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin/New York, pp 71–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Kay P (2004) Pragmatic aspects of grammatical constructions. In: Horn L, Ward G (eds) The handbook of pragmatics. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 675–700

    Google Scholar 

  • Kay P, Michaelis LA (2008) Constructional meaning and compositionality. In: Maienborn C, von Heusinger K, Portner P (eds) Semantics: an international handbook of natural language meaning. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin/New York, pp 2271–2297

    Google Scholar 

  • Knott A (2001) Semantic and pragmatic relations and their intended effects. In: Sanders T, Schilperoord J, Spooren W (eds) Text representation: linguistic and psycholinguistic aspects. Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 27–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer A (1977) What “must” and “can” must and can mean. Linguist Philos 1:337–355, republished in Kratzer 2012: 4–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer A (1981) The notional category of modality. In: Eikmeyer H-J, Rieser H (eds) Words, worlds, and contexts: new approaches in word semantics. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin/New York (Republished in Kratzer 2012: 27–69), pp 38–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer A (1991) Modality. In: von Stechow A, Wunderlich D (eds) Semantik/Semantics: an international handbook of contemporary research. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin/New York, pp 639–650

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer A (2012) Modals and conditionals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kronning H (1996) Modalité, cognition et polysémie: sémantique du verbe modal devoir. Uppsala University Press, Uppsala

    Google Scholar 

  • Kronning H (2001a) Pour une tripartition des emplois du modal devoir. In: Dendale P, van der Auwera J (eds) Les verbes modaux. Cahiers Chronos, vol 8. Rodopi, Amsterdam, pp 67–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Kronning H (2001b) Au-delà du déontique et de l’épistémique. In: Prandi M, Ramat P (eds) Semiotica e linguistica. Per ricordare Maria Elisabeth Conte. Franco Angeli, Milan, pp 97–118

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow P (1999) Semantics, tense and time. An essay in the metaphysics of natural language. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan WG (1994) Modality and meaning. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mann WC, Thompson SA (1987) Rhetorical structure theory: a theory of text organization. Technical report. USC Information Sciences Institute

    Google Scholar 

  • Miecznikowski J (2011) Construction types and argumentative functions of possibility modals: evidence from Italian. In: Eemeren FH, Garssen B, Godden D, Mitchell G (eds) Proceedings of the 7th conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation. Sic Sat, Amsterdam, pp 1284–1297

    Google Scholar 

  • Moeschler J (1989) Modélisation du dialogue. Représentation de l’inférence argumentative. Paris, Hermes

    Google Scholar 

  • Nauze FD (2008) Modality in typological perspective. Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuyts J (2001a) Epistemic modality, language, and conceptualization: a cognitive-pragmatic perspective. John Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nuyts J (2001b) Subjectivity as an evidential dimension in epistemic modal expressions. Journal of Pragmatics 33(3):383–400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nuyts J (2006) Modality: overview and linguistic issues. In: Frawley W (ed) The Expression of Modality. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin/New York, pp 1–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuyts J, Byloo P, Diepeveen J (2010) On deontic modality, directivity, and mood: the case of Dutch mogen and moeten. J Pragmat 42(1):16–34. doi:10.1016/j.pragma.2009.05.012

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer F (1986) Mood and modality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmieri R (2014) Corporate argumentation in takeover bids. John Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papafragou A (1998) Inference and word meaning: The case of modal auxiliaries. Lingua 105:1–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papafragou A (2000) Modality: issues in the semantics-pragmatics interface. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1998 [1931]) Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. In: Hartshorne C, Weiss P, Burks AW (eds). Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietrandrea P (2005) Epistemic modality. John Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinto RC (1996) The relation of argument to inference. In: van Benthem J, van Eemeren FH, Grootendorst R, Veltman F (eds) Logic and argumentation. North-Holland, Oxford/New York/Tokyo

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto RC (2001) Generalizing the notion of argument. In: Pinto R (ed) Argument, inference and dialectic. Collected papers on informal logic. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 10–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Portner P (2009) Modality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach H (1947) Elements of symbolic logic. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rigotti E (2005) Congruity theory and argumentation. Stud Commun Sci (Special Issue: Argumentation in Dialogic Interaction):75–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Rigotti E (2008) Locus a causa finali. L’analisi Linguistica e Letteraria XVI(Special Issue: Word meaning in argumentative dialogue):559–576

    Google Scholar 

  • Rigotti E (2009) Whether and how classical topics can be revived in the contemporary theory of argumentation. In: van Eemeren FH, Garssen B (eds) Pondering on problems of argumentation. Springer, New York, pp 157–178

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rigotti E, Greco Morasso S (2010) Comparing the argumentum model of topics to other contemporary approaches to argument schemes: the procedural and material components. Argumentation 24(4):489–512

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts C (1989) Modal subordination and pronominal anaphora in discourse. Linguist Philos 6:683–721

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rocci A (2000) L’interprétation épistémique du futur en italien et en français: une analyse procédurale. Cahiers de Linguistique Française 22:241–266

    Google Scholar 

  • Rocci A (2005a) La Modalità epistemica tra semantica e argomentazione. I.S.U Università Cattolica, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Rocci A (2005b) On the nature of the epistemic readings of the Italian modal verbs: the relationship between propositionality and inferential discourse relations. In: Hollebrandse B, van Hout A (eds) Crosslinguistic views on tense, aspect and modality. Rodopi, Amsterdam/New York, pp 229–246

    Google Scholar 

  • Rocci A (2009) Doing discourse analysis with possible worlds. In: Renkema J (ed) Discourse, of course. An overview of research in discourse studiesi. Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia, pp 15–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Rocci, Andrea, and Elena Musi. 2014. From modal semantics to discourse: exploring the functioning of the adjective “possibile” in a corpus of Italian financial news. In: Blochowiak J, Grisot C, Laenzlinger C, Durrlemann-Tame S (eds) Papers dedicated to Jacques Moeschler, Geneva, pp 1–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross JR (1969) Auxiliaries as main verbs. In: Todd W (ed) Studies in philosophical linguistics (Series 1). Great Expectations Press, Evanston, pp 77–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (2005) What is an institution? J Inst Econ 1:1–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1969) Speech acts. An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Seuren PAM (1985) Discourse semantics. Blackwell, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Snoeck Henkemans F (2001) Argumentation, explanation and causality: an exploration of current linguistic approaches to textual relations. In: Sanders T, Schilperoord J, Spooren W (eds) Text representation: linguistic and psycholinguistic aspects. John Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia, pp 231–246

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Squartini M (2004) Disentangling evidentiality and epistemic modality in Romance. Lingua 114(7):873–895

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Squartini M (2008) Lexical vs. grammatical evidentiality in French and Italian. Linguistics 46(5):917–947

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sweetser E (1990) From etymology to pragmatics: metaphorical and cultural aspects of semantic structure. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge/New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Talmy L (1985) Force dynamics in language and thought. In: Eilfort WH, Kroeber PD, Peterson KL (eds) Papers from the Parasession on Causatives and Agentivity. Chicago Linguistic Society, Chicago, pp 293–337

    Google Scholar 

  • Traugott EC, Dasher RB (2002) Regularities in semantic change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tseronis A (2009) Qualifying standpoints: stance adverbs as a presentational device for managing the burden of proof. LOT, Utrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Auwera J, Plungian V (1998) Modality’s semantic map. Linguist Typol 2(1):79–124

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren FH (2010) Strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse. John Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren FH, Grootendorst R (1984) Speech acts in argumentative discussions. Foris Publications, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren FH, Grootendorst R (2004) A systematic theory of argumentation: the pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel K, Gillies AS (2011) Might made right. In: Egan A, Weatherson B (eds) Epistemic modality. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 108–130

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • von Wright GH (1963b) Norm and action. A logical enquiry. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • von Wright GH (1963a) Practical inference. Philos Rev 72(2):159. doi:10.2307/2183102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vos A (2006) The philosophy of John Duns Scotus. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walton D (2006) Foundamentals of critical argumentation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton D, Krabbe E (1995) Commitment in dialogue: basic concepts of interpersonal Reasoning. State University of New York Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Webber B, Stone M, Joshi A, Knott A (2003) Anaphora and discourse structure. Comput Linguist 29(4):545–587

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werner T (2005) You do what you gotta do, or why “must” implies “will.” In: Georgala E, Howel J (eds) Proceedings of SALT XV, pp 294–308. http://elanguage.net/journals/index.php/salt/article/download/15.294/1766. Accessed 13 Oct 2016

  • Wertheimer R (1972) The significance of sense: meaning, modality, and morality. Contemporary philosophy. Cornell University Press, Ithaca/London

    Google Scholar 

  • White AR (1975) Modal thinking. B. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Willett T (1988) A cross-linguistic survey of the grammaticization of evidentiality. Stud Lang 12(2):51–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wurmbrand S (1999) Modal verbs must be raising verbs. In: Bird S, Carnie A, Haugen J, Norquest P (eds) Proceedings of the West Coast conference on formal linguistics 18. Cascadilla, Somerville, pp 599–612

    Google Scholar 

  • Yarza I (2000) L’attualità dell’etica di Aristotele. In: Brock SL (ed) L’attualità Di Aristotele. Armando Editore, Rome, pp 33–52

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rocci, A. (2017). Types of Conversational Backgrounds and Arguments. In: Modality in Argumentation. Argumentation Library, vol 29. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-1063-1_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-1063-1_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-024-1061-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-024-1063-1

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics