Skip to main content

The Sociality of Conscience and Rawls’s Liberalism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Politics, Religion and Political Theology

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in Philosophy, Religion and Public Life ((BSPR,volume 6))

  • 579 Accesses

Abstract

To what extent is individual conscience social in character? Anti-individualist critics have taken issue with the individualistic account of conscience that they find prominent in liberalism. I consider Rawls’s accounts of conscience and the liberty of conscience with a view to understanding the role that sociality might play in the formation and significance of conscience. I defend Rawls against these anti-individualist critics. However, I demonstrate that Rawls’s account of conscience remains bound to a specific metaphysics of the person that is at odds with the anti-foundationalist aims of political liberalism. I argue that, in place of this metaphysics, liberals should adopt a social ontology of the self.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Defenders of conscience argue that it is the means through which we take on and adopt the justified norms and expectations of those with whom we share our social life, or of the voice of divinity. See Howard (2014). Critics aim to show that conscience merely expresses the demands of the disciplining parent (Freud) or the heroic ancestor (Nietzsche), demands that the individual has internalized, falsely (and heteronomously) claiming as their own a voice which does not belong to them.

  2. 2.

    Sorabji (2014) argues that the sort of shared knowledge that “conscience” denotes is that of “sharing knowledge with oneself of a defect,” so that “Conscience is a form of self-awareness that would always remain personal” (Sorabji 2014, 2).

  3. 3.

    This idea animates the recent account of the demand for toleration in Leiter (2013).

  4. 4.

    See, in this vein, Nussbaum 2008, 19–20.

  5. 5.

    I focus on Vischer 2010.

  6. 6.

    In general, I assume broad familiarity with Rawls ’s views, though I have made some efforts to avoid relying too much on his technical terminology, and to provide independent explanations of key ideas.

  7. 7.

    We find such accounts in both Rawls  1971, 205–211 and Rawls 2005, 310–324.

  8. 8.

    Leiter argues that religion merits no special protection, but should be tolerated on the grounds that it is an expression of conscience.

  9. 9.

    The fact that Rawls believes individuals may not even have such fundamental convictions is made explicit in his account of the reasoning of the parties in the original position. See, for example, Rawls  1971, 206 and Rawls 2005, 311.

  10. 10.

    For example at Rawls 2005, 11.

  11. 11.

    Spinoza argues for a general freedom of thought, but concludes that the state is within its rights in establishing and promoting a single state religion. Spinoza 1951, 261, 252. On this issue, see Israel 2000, 105.

  12. 12.

    For a critique of such conceptions, see Howard 2014.

  13. 13.

    Rawls  2005, 318–320. In addition to this appeal to self-respect, Rawls identifies two other grounds for the liberty of conscience : the contribution that liberty of conscience and the other basic liberties make first to the stability of justice as fairness, and second to a well-ordered society.

  14. 14.

    The categorical imperative procedure “specifies the content of the moral law as it applies to us as reasonable and rational persons in the natural world, endowed with conscience and moral sensibility, and affected by, but not determined by, our natural desires and inclinations” (Rawls 2000, 164). It bears noting that Rawls’s lectures provide little guidance on this question too. We find the only other mention of conscience in the lectures in the context of a discussion of Hume , in which Rawls provides a rough outline of Butler’s view of the source and function of conscience.

  15. 15.

    In general, Rawls argues that “from the standpoint of justice as fairness, [moral or religious] obligations are self-imposed” since “they are not bonds laid down by this conception of justice” (Rawls 1971, 206). See also Rawls 2005, 33–34. However, this notion is at odds with one plausible conception of moral obligation and of conscience, according to which the roots of our obligations lie in others or the demands they make on us, and we do not simply have those obligations because we claim them as our own or take responsibility for them.

  16. 16.

    Vischer 2010, 4. Vischer does not reject the need for nondiscrimination laws entirely, arguing that the Civil Rights Act, for example, is justified because the extraordinary and significant forms of discrimination that predominated in the south were seriously detrimental to the “common good.” See Vischer 2010, 26–29.

  17. 17.

    On finding he appropriate balance among the basic liberties, see Rawls 1971, 203.

  18. 18.

    Indeed, Rawls goes out of his way to stress that, within the original position, individuals need not “think of themselves as having [moral or religious] obligations” (Rawls  1971, 206. See also Rawls 2005, 311).

  19. 19.

    See especially Rawls  1971, 458 ff. For the later account, see Rawls 2005, xv–xvii especially.

  20. 20.

    For a helpful introduction to the central ideas of social ontology and its connection to the self, see Ikäheimo and Laitinen 2011, 1–21.

  21. 21.

    Searle 1995, 1. Along similar lines, “We need not look for any inherent features or properties that are the markers or conditions of personhood. Rather, someone is a person (in the relevant sense) if he is in fact caught up in a network of discursive holdings—that is, if others successfully recognize him, through speech acts containing vocative moments, as a user and receiver of speech acts, or as the kind of being who can transform the normative status of others and have his own normative status transformed through discourse with other community members.” Kukla and Lance 2009, 192.

  22. 22.

    For such an expressive conception of reason, see Brandom 1994.

  23. 23.

    Such an account need not depend on a specious teleology by appealing to a purpose inherent to human nature. For one account of the sort of historical change I have in mind, see Pippin 1999, 73–77.

  24. 24.

    Though, it bears noting, that it is unclear whether he understands reason to be at work, progressively realized, in history, or whether he understands these domains to be only contingently connected.

  25. 25.

    See especially Rawls  2005, xliii.

  26. 26.

    Of course, Rawls acknowledges the Kantian roots of his idea of the person even in Political Liberalism . See, for example, Rawls 2005, 48n1. I am challenging the extent to which we can separate out a political conception of the self from the comprehensive framework in which these ideas have their ultimate roots.

References

  • Brandom RB (1994) Making it explicit: reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard J (2014) Conscience in moral life: rethinking how our convictions structure self and society. Rowman & Littlefield, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ikäheimo H, Laitinen A (2011) Recognition and social ontology. Brill, Leiden

    Google Scholar 

  • Israel JI (2000) Spinoza, Locke, and the enlightenment battle for toleration. In: Grell OP, Porter R (eds) Toleration in enlightenment Europe. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukla R, Lance M (2009) ‘Yo!’ and ‘Lo!’: the pragmatic topography of the space of reasons. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Leiter B (2013) Why tolerate religion? Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke J (1990) A letter concerning toleration. Prometheus Books, Amherst

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum M (2008) Liberty of conscience. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pippin RB (1999) Modernism as a philosophical problem. Blackwell, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (2000) Lectures on the history of moral philosophy. Herman B (ed). Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (2005) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1995) The construction of social reality. The Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji R (2014) Conscience through the ages. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza B (1951) Theologico-political treatise. In: R. H. M. Elwes (trans) The chief works of Spinoza, vol 1. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor C (1979) Hegel and modern society. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vischer RK (2010) Conscience and the common good. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Timothy L. Brownlee .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Brownlee, T.L. (2017). The Sociality of Conscience and Rawls’s Liberalism. In: Speight, C., Zank, M. (eds) Politics, Religion and Political Theology. Boston Studies in Philosophy, Religion and Public Life, vol 6. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-1082-2_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics