Skip to main content

The Bargaining Context of General Institution Reform

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Parse of China
  • 304 Accesses

Abstract

In essence, the political behavior of human society is similar to a two-person game in a strict sense, because in most contexts, there is no third way for the generalized political behavior to choose. In view of the theoretical needs of generalization and classification, the strict two-person game actually rules out the effect of the competitive factor of the market sense, in which people have to always subject themselves to a simple choice of “yes or no” logic rather than the diversity selection.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Brandenburger, A and E Dekel (1993). Hierarchies of beliefs and common Knowledge, Journal of Economic Theory, 59, 189–198.

  2. 2.

    If we say, for example, there is an earthquake in the process of the game, obviously, the outcomes will have nothing to do with the strategies of the two player as well as the theoretical analysis.

  3. 3.

    The unchanged identity here is also the part of Harsanyi doctrine: the logic that “all rational economy men have the same behavior in the same situation”.

  4. 4.

    Here, \( i = a,e \) represent two persons of the bargaining, namely, Adam and Eve, in the nice story of Binmore’s book (2005). And the related statements also copy from him above.

  5. 5.

    A famous case is the empirical research on the behaviors of two brain injurers caused by the accidents in 1848 and 1950 provided by Antonio Damasio. The parties Cage and Elliot seemed to not lose the rational ability as a whole man after return from the specific brain injury, but they showed the typical characteristics of autistics due to certain amnesia, and finally failed to integrate in the society. From this sense, they lost the self-existence value as a social person—of course, it is “our” point of view.

  6. 6.

    See the descriptions of the three conditions about the set \( \Omega \) at the beginning of the Appendix of Chap. 4.

  7. 7.

    On the several steps of transformation listed, here is a common saying. And it is the so called “Harsanyi Transformation”. The specific mathematical expression and logic can refer to general teaching materials.

  8. 8.

    Here, the players’ belief play an important role in games. Details can refers to Brandemburger’s study (2015) and also to Aumann, R (1987). Correlated equilibrium as an expression of Bayesian rationality. Econometrica, 55, 1–18.

  9. 9.

    It can be seen more clearly from the story characterized in Chap. 1.

  10. 10.

    The production relation is the concept in Marx’s sense. According to the context of the political bargaining game in the book, it is also the social relation.

  11. 11.

    Here, \( B_{reform} \left( {G_{o} ,n,X,\Omega } \right) \) is simplified to \( B\left( {G_{o} ,X,\Omega } \right) \) in which the omitted n’s players is clearly.

  12. 12.

    The comprehensive understanding can return to the detailed discussion about Buchanan’s theory of transaction politics (1962) in Chap. 2 of the book.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yilun Tong .

Appendix: Definition of the Bargaining Game of General Institution Reform

Appendix: Definition of the Bargaining Game of General Institution Reform

Next, according to the characteristics of the two-person bargaining of political behavior and the institution expression argued above, we will give the definition of institution reform of bargaining in the sense of the book and its mathematical structure based on the context of the generalized transaction.

Institution reform refers to a social bargaining process of the two-person game. Its relationship with institution concept itself is: the status quo of the bargaining of institution reform is the initial institution, and its result is the equilibrium of the bargaining of reform and emerges as a new institution. As a dynamic description of institution, here, institution reform mainly emphasizes the process and occurrence mechanism of institution evolution. According to Definition 5.1 of Chapter 5, social institution could be taken as a set of people’s social behavior norms and expressed as a 2D topology \( G_{o} \left( {n,X,\xi } \right) \). In the standard two-person game context of the chapter, it means the workers and the farmers in the social member set \( i \in \left\{ {1,2} \right\} \) will obtain the generalized benefits (or punishment) \( \xi_{i} (x_{i} ) \in R^{1} \) when being engaged in the social behavior \( x_{i} \in X \), \( (i = 1,2) \) (or we could also write it as \( u_{i} = \xi_{i} \in R^{1} \), \( i = 1,2 \)).

As a series of contracts or norms, social institution gives people’s current social behaviors corresponding social value through the inherited or realistic public rights. The economic calculation of the social values is the generalized benefit of the book. According to Definition 5.2 and Eqs. (5.1) and (5.2), the social behavior set X is a convex set in which 1 (workers) is symmetry to 2 (farmers). In association with the initial institution of the status quo, here, the concept of convex implies the social norm \( G_{o} :X \to R^{1} \) has the mutual correlation of social behaviors, which can be properly understood from the concept of generalized benefit by the example of the political philosophy. For the given behavior \( x_{i} \in X \) of any party, the corresponding benefits of two parties are complementary. That is to say, the sum of the generalized benefits of two parties is a certain constant. If we simply written it as the integer 1, there will be \( \xi_{1} (x_{i} ) + \xi_{2} (x_{i} ) = 1 \) \( (\xi_{i} \in [0,1],i = 1,2) \). At this time, the social value about “absolutely equality” is essentially that \( \forall \,x_{i} \in X,i = 1,2 \), social institution \( G_{o} :x_{i} \to \xi_{i} \in R^{1} \) will ensure \( \xi_{1} = \xi_{2} = 1/2 \). And the social value of the efficiency is obviously contained in the equilibrium once the bargaining deals.

According to the rational nature of generalized transaction, a bargaining of institution reform from \( G_{o} \) to \( G_{n} \) caused by the realistic demand can be regarded as a process of complete information within the scope of the book. It means the worker and the farmer fully understand that: if the institution \( G_{o} \) is changed to be \( G_{n} \), both parties will get the Pareto improvementFootnote 12 after the reform. Here, we can assume \( G_{o} \cap G_{n} \ne \varnothing \), which means the bargaining reform is the reform of a limited (or single) institution rather than complete negation of overall institutions, so as to maintain the continuity of the reform process. In fact, the process of making part reform on the institution \( G_{o} \) to reach the consent \( G_{n} \), actually, is an intuitive and realistic description of two parties doing the bargaining around the expected benefits resulted from the reform. If the single institution identified by two sides is written as \( G_{o}^{S} \), and a corresponding possible new institution is written as \( G_{n}^{S} \), it is easy to understand:

Definition 6.1

The reform of a single institution \( G_{o}^{S} \) is the mapping of a bargaining game \( B^{S} :G_{o}^{S} \to G_{n}^{S} \), in which \( G_{o}^{S} \subseteq G_{o} \), \( G_{n}^{S} \subseteq G_{n} \).

Obviously, if \( \overline{{G_{o} \cap G_{n} }} = \varnothing \), then \( B^{S} \) means no-reform. If \( G_{o} \cap G_{n} = \varnothing \) and \( G_{n}^{S} = G_{n} \), \( B^{S} \) means radical reform. If \( G_{o} \cap G_{n} \ne \varnothing \) and \( G_{n}^{S} \subset G_{n} \), \( B^{S} \) means the gradual reform which may composed of a continuous several such small reform together.

If the universal set of all possible schemes of player i about institution reform is written as \( S_{i} = \left\{ {\omega_{j} ,s_{j} } \right\} \), where \( s_{j} \) comes from \( G_{o}^{S} \) and makes up the new institution \( G_{n}^{S} \) with the probability of \( \omega_{j} \). The bargaining of the institution reform is written as \( B^{reform} (n,d,G_{o} ,S,\Omega ) \), where \( n = \{ 1,2\} \); \( d = (d_{1} ,d_{2} ) \) is the status quo of two bargainers’ benefit under the initial institution \( G_{o} \); \( S = \left\{ {(s_{1} ,s_{2} );s_{i} = \sum\nolimits_{j \in J} {\omega_{j} s_{j} } \in S_{i} \subseteq G_{n} ,i \in \{ 1,2\} ,\sum\nolimits_{j = 1}^{J} {\omega_{j} } = 1} \right\} \) is the bargaining set composed of all strategic propositions of two sides about the institution reform scheme; \( \Omega = U(S) \) is the joint utility function (temporarily being understood as the expected utility function of V-N-M), which is based on the preference relations of each side over S, \( u_{i} :s_{j} \to {\mathbb{R}}_{ + }^{1} \) (\( s_{j} \in S_{j} \), \( i = 1,2 \)), corresponding to the bargaining set S of institution reform and can also be written as \( B^{reform} :S \Rightarrow\Omega \subset {\mathbb{R}}_{ + }^{2} \) or:

$$ \Omega = \left\{ {(u_{1} ,u_{2} );u_{i} = u_{i} (s_{i} ),s_{i} \in S_{i} ,i = 1,2} \right\} $$

Or, \( \Omega = \left\{ {(u_{1} ,\phi (u_{1} ));u_{1} = u_{1} (s_{1} ),s_{1} \in S} \right\} \) (\( \phi \) is the boundary curve of S).

Traditionally, it can be known from the discussion of the convexity of the social behavior set S, the social association of the institution norm \( {\text{G}}_{\text{o}} \) and \( G_{n} \), Axiom 6.2 of the strict two-person bargaining, Axiom 6.4 of bounded rationality, and Axiom 6.5 of non-violent bargaining that the bargaining set S and its set of the joint utility function \( \Omega \) meet the following properties:

  1. (a)
    $$ \Omega \subseteq \left\{ {(u_{1} ,u_{2} ):u_{i} > d_{i} ,i = 1,2} \right\} $$
    (6.1)
  2. (b)
    $$ \Omega \cap \left\{ {\left( {u_{1} ,u_{2} } \right):u_{i} > d_{i},i = 1,2} \right\} \ne \varnothing $$
    (6.2)
  3. (c)
    $$ (d \le v \le u) \wedge (u \in U) \Rightarrow (v \in\Omega ) $$
    (6.3)

Here, (a) means that the bargaining set is superior to the status quo; (b) means the bargaining set can be Pareto improvement; (c) means the bargaining set is a compact set; the union of three equations means the boundary curve \( \phi \) of the bargaining set is a continuous and differentiable concave function; or, when the “trade objects” in the specific political negotiation are different items of institution reform, Participants 1 and 2 have the rational preference for the negotiation content of institution reform. Thus, there is a continuous convex set \( \Omega \). Generally, in the case that n is clearly specified, we simply write the bargaining game of the institution reform as \( B^{reform} (G_{o} ,d,S,\Omega ) \), which is to emphasize that the final result or equilibrium of the reform negotiation depends on the status quo \( d = (d_{1} ,d_{2} ) \) of \( G_{o} \), and the nature of the bargaining set S. Obviously, under the condition of Nash bargaining, the bargaining game of institution reform in the book is generalized as Nash bargaining demand solution. Thus, there is:

Definition 6.2

Nash bargaining solution \( B^{reform} :G_{o} \to G_{n} \) of an institution reform meets (Fig. 6.3):

Fig. 6.3
figure 3

The behavior space under the institution G0

$$ B^{re} \left( {G_{o} ,d,S,\Omega } \right) = {\text{agr}}\mathop {\text{Max}}\limits_{{(s_{1} ,s_{2} ) \in S}} (u_{1} (s_{1} ) - d_{1} )(u_{2} (s_{2} ) - d_{2} ) $$

Furtherly, from asymmetry Axiom 6.3, we can assume that there is \( \pi (\alpha ,\beta ) \in (0,1) \), here \( \alpha \) and \( \beta \) (\( \alpha ,\beta \in R_{ + }^{1} \)) are the social indexes of 1 and 2 respectively (the next chapter will discuss in more detail), so as to have:

Definition 6.3

The asymmetric Nash bargaining solution \( B^{reform} :G_{o} \to G_{n} \) of an institution reform game meets:

$$ B^{re} \left( {G_{o} ,d,S,\Omega } \right) = {\text{agr}}\mathop {\text{Max}}\limits_{{s_{i} \in S,u_{i} \ge d_{i} }} (u_{1} (s_{1} ) - d_{1} )^{\pi } (u_{2} (s_{2} ) - d_{2} )^{1 - \pi } . $$

Thus, through the definitions of institution, institution reform, and relevant variables above, we complete the description of a bargaining game about the institution reform and its equilibrium concept, so that to simplify the mechanism of institution change as a bargaining process of political behavior of both sides about the institution reform profits.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Truth and Wisdom Press and Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Tong, Y. (2017). The Bargaining Context of General Institution Reform. In: Parse of China. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-4479-3_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics