Skip to main content
  • 74 Accesses

Abstract

…[O]nly slovenly souls abandon what once made an absolute impression upon them. (CUP 590)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See Stanley Cavell, Conditions Handsome and Unhandsome: The Constitution of Emersonian Perfectionism (University of Chicago Press, 1990), p. 5. Hereafter CHU.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Walden (V, 2), cited in Stephen Mulhall, Stanley Cavell: Philosophys Recounting of the Ordinary (Oxford University Press, 1994a), p. 256.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Stanley Cavell, The Senses of Walden (New York: Viking, 1972), pp. 51–2.

    Google Scholar 

  4. David Owen, ‘Cultural Diversity and the Conversation of Justice: Reading Cavell on Political Voice and the Expression of Consent’, in Political Theory, vol. 27 no. 5 (1999), p. 581.

    Google Scholar 

  5. R. G. Collingwood, The Principles of Art (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1938); hereafter PA.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Aaron Ridley, R. G. Collingwood: a Philosophy of Art (London: Phoenix, 1998), p. 7. The quotation from PA is on p. 216.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Kierkegaard’s main discussion of the ‘crowd’ or ‘public’ is in Two Ages. For a discussion that compares Kierkegaard and Nietzsche on this point, see Merold Westphal, ‘Kierkegaard’s Sociology’, in his Kierkegaards Critique of Reason and Society, (paperback edn) (University Park, PA.: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1991), pp. 43–59.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See PA, especially ch. 2. Ridley provides a good summary on pp. 10–17. See also Christopher Janaway, ‘Arts and Crafts in Plato and Collingwood’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, vol. 50 (1992), pp. 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Compare here Wittgenstein’s comment on philosophy’s ‘decline’ into a subject with a ‘method’: ‘The nimbus of philosophy has been lost. For we now have a method of doing philosophy, and can speak of skilful philosophers … But once a method has been found the opportunities for the expression of personality are correspondingly restricted’ (Wittgensteins Lectures, Cambridge 1930–1932, ed. Desmond Lee (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980), p. 21).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Hereafter SE. In what follows, I use the same translation used by Conant: that found in Friedrich Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (Cambridge University Press, 1983). Conant’s article, Nietzsche’s Perfectionism: A Reading of “Schopenhauer as Educator”’ (hereafter NP), is forthcoming in Richard Schacht (ed.), Nietzsches Postmoralism (Cambridge University Press). My citations are from page numbers in unpublished manuscript form. I am grateful to Stephen Mulhall and Michael Weston for bringing this article to my attention.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Friedrich Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human, vol. 1, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (Cambridge University Press, 1986), sect. 162.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Timothy Gould, Hearing Things: Voice and Method in the Writing of Stanley Cavell (University of Chicago Press, 1998), p. 148. Gould adds that this feature ‘points most directly toward the analogy of reading with psychoanalytic therapy’ (ibid.), but there is obviously no reason why the idea of ‘being read by’ a text need necessarily go in the direction of psychoanalysis.

    Google Scholar 

  14. For an interesting discussion of this, see George Pattison, `If Kierkegaard is right about reading, why read Kierkegaard?’, in Niels Jergen Cappelarn and Jon Stewart (eds), Kierkegaard Revisited (Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1997), pp. 291–309, esp. pp. 299–301.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Edward F. Mooney, ‘Exemplars, Inwardness, and Belief: Kierkegaard on Indirect Communication’, in Robert L. Perkins (ed.) International Kierkegaard Commentary: Concluding Unscientific Postscript (Macon, Georgia: Mercer University Press, 1997), p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Pia Ssltof t, ‘The Unhappy Lover of Subjectivity: Is the Pseudonym Johannes Climacus an Unequivocal Figure?’, trans. M. G. Piety, in Niels Jtergen Cappelern and Hermann Deuser (eds) Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook 1996 (Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1996), p. 259.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Several recent commentators have written on the social dimensions of Kierkegaard’s thought, much of this work taking to task the common stereotype of Kierkegaard as asocial individualist. See, for example, George Pattison and Steven Shakespeare (eds), Kierkegaard: The Self in Society (London: Macmillan, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  18. For a recent argument which, although it makes no reference to Climacus, proceeds to the same conclusion, see Alexander Nehamas, The Art of Living: Socratic Reflections from Plato to Foucault (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press, 1998), ch. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  19. I borrow this phrase from David Cain: see his ‘Treasure in Earthen Vessels: Johannes Climacus on Humor and Faith’, in Niels Thulstrup and Marie Mikulova Thulstrup (eds), Irony and Humor in SOren Kierkegaard (Copenhagen: C. A. Reitzels Forlag, 1988), p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2000 John Lippitt

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lippitt, J. (2000). Moral Perfectionism and Exemplars. In: Humour and Irony in Kierkegaard’s Thought. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230598652_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics